Shattering Chain When the Sovereign Will Not: Responsibility to Protect and the Use of Military Intervention to Stop Slavery

AuthorEthan A. Dazelle
PositionUniversity of Massachusetts School of Law
Pages427-473
e Indonesian Journal of International & Comparative Law
ISSN: 2338-7602; E-ISSN: 2338-770X
http://www.ijil.org
© 2017 e Institute for Migrant Rights Press
e author would like to extend his thanks to Professors Richard Peltz-Steele and
Jeremiah Ho for their insights and encouragement in writing this piece, to Professor
Francis Rudko for her instruction on the various human rights systems and public
international law generally, and to his long-time partner, Karen Abouhamad, for the
necessary prodding and poking to write down what he is always prattling on about.
SHATTERING CHAINS WHEN THE
SOVEREIGN WILL NOT
RESPONSIBILITY TO PROTECT AND THE USE OF MILITARY
INTERVENTION TO STOP SLAVERY
Ethan A. Dazelle
University of Massachusetts School of Law
E-mail: edazelle@umassd.edu
As an emerging international norm that recognizes genocide as sucient ground
for circumventing the fundamental principle of sovereignty, which generally for-
bids humanitarian intervention, the Responsibility to Protect (R2P) should and
does allow for the legal use of military intervention by the international commu-
nity whenever a sovereign State and practicing, tolerating, or failing to eliminate
slavery that is publicly and openly practiced. Intervention under these terms
against a legally-institutionalized form of slavery is not only fully compatible
with the present obligations of U.N. member States, including the permanent
members of the U.N. Security Council, but demanded under the U.N. Charter
Article 1, the Slavery Convention of 1926, the Universal Declaration of Human
Rights, and other sources of humanitarian obligation. us, R2P necessitates
a response that fully resolves the manifest failure of the sovereign. Such a re-
sponse would be a multilateral, Security Council-authorized operation centered
on reacting in force to free slaves and to dismantle the infrastructure of that
extraordinarily peculiar institution, followed immediately by reconstructing the
territory, and preventing further crimes against humanity.
Keywords: Humanitarian Intervention, Use of Force, Human Rights, Law of War,
Global Governance.
IV Indonesian Journal of International & Comparative Law 427-73 (Julyl 2017)
428
Dazelle
I. INTRODUCTION
Liberty is the power that we have over ourselves.1 Hugo Grotius
He said that raping me is his prayer to God. I said, “What you’re
doing to me is wrong…” And he said, “No, it’s allowed.2 F
December 6, 2015, marked the 150th anniversary of the adoption of
the irteenth Amendment outlawing slavery in the United States.3
In Europe, the open practice of slavery and the slave trade had been
abolished even longer.4e international community at large has con-
demned the existence of de jure slavery, the General Assembly of the
United Nations having approved the Convention for the Suppression
of the Trac in Persons and of the Exploitation of the Prostitution of
Others in 19495 and the amended Slavery Convention in 1959.6 Slavery
practiced systematically and tolerated openly by any member of the
international community is dicult to fathom in the face of such per-
vasive condemnation.
And yet slavery of this sort is not dead, however, and neither are
1. 1 E D  , W B C W P L 329
(1981). e quote is a more popular adaption from Grotius’s original phraseol-
ogy on liberty in his seminal work On the Law of War and Peace: “[T]he power
we have over ourselves, which is called liberty.” H G, O  L
 W  P 19 (Louise Loomis trans., New York, Walter J. Black 1949)
(1625).
2. Rukmini Callimachi, ISIS Enshrines a eology of Rape, N.Y. T (Aug. 14,
2015), http://www.nytimes.com/2015/08/14/world/middleeast/isis-enshrines-
a-theology-of-rape.html.
3. See C. R. S., T C   U S: A-
  I 30 (Government Printing Oce et al. eds., 2013).
An online version of the treatise is available at http://www.gpo.gov/fdsys/pkg/
GPO-CONAN-2013/pdf/GPO-CONAN-2013.pdf.
4. See e Struggle to End Slavery: A Timeline, D U. (Oct. 22, 2014), https://
community.dur.ac.uk/4schools.resources/Slavery4/timeline.htm [https://per-
ma.cc/R82F-TG46] (dates of full abolition: England 1833, France 1848, and
Spain 1811 only in continental Europe).
5. Convention for the Suppression of the Trac in Persons and of the Exploita-
tion of the Prostitution of Others, July 25, 1951, 96 U.N.T.S. 271.
6. Slavery Convention, Sept. 25, 1926, 60 L.N.T.S. 253.
429
Shattering Chains When the Sovereign Will Not
Dazelle
the victims who still nd themselves living in literal chains pressed
upon them by institutions. e Islamic State of Iraq and Syria (ISIS)
has implemented a bureaucratized form of slavery in which several
thousand women of the Yazidi racial minority are shipped, inspected,
registered, and sold or resold as property in an open market by their
“owners.7 is is not unseen smuggling that cannot be traced, nor is
it practiced without knowledge by the States of Syria or Iraq, let alone
the international community at large. It is blatant, open, and widely
documented, with pamphlets establishing best practices and exchanges
made under contracts approved by a judicial system.8
Despite this stinging reminder, institutionalized slavery has receded
from the light of public scrutiny in the West, and exists outside the
public consciousness, believing it to have been banished more than a
century and a half ago. It also has not been eradicated as a defunct
feature of pre-modern states, despite what some political and economic
theories maintain. e tragedy of the Yazidi racial minority is empirical
evidence, a rarity in social science, that overt slavery supported or
tolerated by the State is possible, even in the Information Age. It is
capable of returning despite perhaps being the issue that garners the
most explicit international consensus as to its condemnation and the
general obligation to oppose it. A failure to oppose slavery of this
form with the absolute strongest means available is to surrender the
legitimacy of the international community’s responsibility to protect
the rights of all humanity.
For the international community, the strongest means of opposition
against slavery, or any crime against humanity, is military humanitarian
intervention (MHI). Under international law, MHI is the most
controversial response to crimes against humanity in the 21st century.9
Foregoing the feasibility of MHI, any policy of the U.N. member States,
especially the Security Council, purporting to use such intervention
should also articulate institutionalized slavery as a supreme failure
of the State it is practiced in. Such failure should be akin to genocide
7. Callimachi, supra note 2.
8. Id.
9. See I’ C’  I  S S, T R-
  P, ¶ 1.38 A/57/303, at 8 (Aug. 14, 2001) [hereinaer I’
C’, RP R].

To continue reading

Request your trial

VLEX uses login cookies to provide you with a better browsing experience. If you click on 'Accept' or continue browsing this site we consider that you accept our cookie policy. ACCEPT