IF WE CONFESS OUR SINS

Date01 August 2019
DOIhttp://doi.org/10.1111/iere.12390
Published date01 August 2019
AuthorFrancisco Silva
INTERNATIONAL ECONOMIC REVIEW
Vol. 60, No. 3, August 2019 DOI: 10.1111/iere.12390
IF WE CONFESS OUR SINS
BYFRANCISCO SILVA1
Ponticia Universidad Catolica de Chile, Chile
I consider a scenario where a social planner suspects that a crime has been committed. There are many suspects
and at most one of them is guilty. I characterize the optimal mechanism for the social planner under different
assumptions with respect to her commitment power. I find that the optimal mechanism is a “confession inducing
mechanism”: Before an investigation, each agent can confess to being guilty in exchange for a reduced pun-
ishment. I find that these mechanisms do better than the traditional trial mechanism because of information
externalities: When an agent credibly confesses his guilt, he reveals everyone else’s innocence.
1. INTRODUCTION
Imagine that there is the suspicion that a crime has been committed. There are Nsuspects
(the agents) and at most one of them is guilty. Each agent knows only whether he is guilty or
innocent. I consider the following question: “What is the best mechanism that a principal can
design if her goal is to punish only the guilty agent?”
The traditional solution is a “trial” mechanism. In a trial mechanism, if the principal suspects
a crime has been committed, she initiates an investigation aimed at obtaining evidence—some
exogenous signal θ, correlated with the agents’ guilt. Based on that evidence θ, the principal
forms beliefs about the guilt of each agent and chooses punishments accordingly: Each agent n
receives a punishment of some xn=dn(θ). However, I argue in this article that these systems
are suboptimal for the principal: She will be able to do better by communicating with the agents
prior to launching an investigation.
The communication takes place as follows: The principal gives each agent n, who is privately
informed of his innocence/guilt, the opportunity to choose some message mnfrom some “mes-
sage set” Mnbefore evidence θhas been collected; then the principal starts an investigation
that produces θ; and, finally, based on message vector m=(m1,...,mN) and on evidence θ,
she chooses a punishment xn=dn(m) for each agent n. Message set M=M1×...×MNand
function d=(d1,...,dN) form a “mechanism” (the trial mechanism is a “special” mechanism
where punishments do not depend on the message mof the agents). The goal of the article is to
study which mechanisms (M,d) are optimal for the principal under two different assumptions
with respect to the principal’s ability to commit to a mechanism: full commitment power and
partial commitment power.
The assumption of full commitment power is the standard one in mechanism design: The
principal can commit to any mechanism (M,d) she chooses. In this setting, I find that the
optimal mechanism is what I call a “confession inducing” mechanism (CIM). A CIM has two
properties. The first property, which is implied by the revelation principle (Myerson, 1979), is
that each agent’s message set is made of only two messages, labeled cand c, that is, Mn={c,c}
Manuscript received November 2017; revised November 2018.
1I would like to thank David Abrams, Martin Besfamille, Mustafa Dogan, Selman Erol, Nicolas Figueroa, Nicholas
Janetos, Sangmok Lee, George Mailath, Steven Matthews, Timofiy Mylovanov, Daniel Neuhann, Qiusha Peng, Andrew
Postlewaite, Bernardo S. da Silveira, Rakesh Vohra, and Yanhao Wei as well as the UPenn’s Micro Lunch seminar
participants for their useful comments. Please address correspondence to: Francisco Silva, Department of Economics,
Pontificia Universidad Catolica de Chile, Vicu˜
na Mackenna 4860, Piso 3. Macul, Santiago, Chile (CL). Phone: +56
948544106. E-mail: franciscosilva@uc.cl
1389
C
(2019) by the Economics Department of the University of Pennsylvania and the Osaka University Institute of Social
and Economic Research Association
1390 SILVA
for all n. Message cis interpreted as a confession, whereas message cis interpreted as a refusal
to confess: In a CIM, each agent is able to confess to being guilty before an investigation takes
place. The second property is that, whenever an agent confesses, his punishment is independent
of what other agents may have reported and of the evidence, that is, dn(c,mn) is independent
of mnand θ(where mnhas the standard interpretation).
This description is reminiscent of two mechanisms that already exist in American law: “self-
reporting,” which exists in environmental law and “plea bargaining” in criminal law. The idea
behind self-reporting in environmental law is that firms that infringe environmental regulations
can contact the corresponding law enforcement authority and self-report this infringement in
exchange for a smaller punishment than the one they would have received if they were later
found guilty. In plea bargaining, defendants are given the chance to confess to having committed
the crime in exchange for a reduced sentence.
In the literature, there have been papers that have highlighted two advantages of CIMs when
compared to trial systems: Kaplow and Shavell (1994) show that CIMs can do better because
they can reduce costs (in a setting with only a single agent, a credible confession eliminates
the need for a costly investigation), and Grossman and Katz (1983) and Siegel and Strulovici
(2018) show that CIMs can do better because they can reduce risk (for example, the risk of
acquitting guilty agents). In the text, I characterize the optimal CIM under the assumption of
full commitment power and show that it is preferred to the trial mechanism but for a different
reason: information externalities. More precisely, there are information externalities that are
generated by each credible confession: When an agent who is guilty confesses, that confession
informs the principal that all other agents are innocent. Therefore, when the principal decides
the punishments of the agents who did not confess, she will not make the mistake of punishing
them. In other words, the fact that it is commonly known that there is at most one guilty
agent implies that the agents’ guilt is correlated, which is what generates these information
externalities.2
The commitment power of the principal can be used to (i) impose small punishments on
agents who are believed to be guilty, and (ii) to punish agents who are believed to be innocent.
To implement the optimal CIM, the principal uses both: by the revelation principle, following
the optimal CIM, each agent confesses if guilty but refuses if innocent. Therefore, the principal
knows that in equilibrium every agent who confesses is guilty and every agent who refuses is
innocent. So, the principal uses (i) to be able to punish agents who have confessed less than
what she would have preferred and uses (ii) to be able to punish agents who have not confessed
more than what she would have wanted. Assumption (ii) seems particularly problematic: it is
hard to see how a mechanism that punishes agents who are known to be innocent could be
implemented. In light of that, I consider the case of partial commitment power, which is defined
to allow the principal to commit to (i) but not to (ii).3
When the principal has partial commitment power, it is as if she is unable to commit not to
renegotiate: The principal cannot commit to punish those she believes are innocent because
both she and the agent would be better off by renegotiating and selecting a smaller punishment.
In this context, the problem of finding the optimal mechanism is more challenging seeing as,
in general, the revelation principle need not follow (see Bester and Strausz, 2000). The main
technical contribution of this article is to show that, even in this context, CIMs are optimal.
The optimal renegotiation proof CIM is, however, different than the optimal CIM when the
principal has full commitment power in two ways. First, it is such that, in equilibrium, agents do
not completely separate, that is, unlike the case with full commitment power, if the agent is guilty,
he randomizes between confessing and not confessing (while the innocent never confesses). This
means that, upon observing a refusal to confess, the principal is no longer certain that the agent
is innocent, which allows her to impose some punishments on nonconfessing agents, which is
2A similar argument has been made to argue in favor of leniency policies as a way to reduce collusion. I review this
literature on the literature review section.
3In Appendix A.2, I also briefly discuss the case where the principal cannot commit to either (i) nor (ii).

To continue reading

Request your trial

VLEX uses login cookies to provide you with a better browsing experience. If you click on 'Accept' or continue browsing this site we consider that you accept our cookie policy. ACCEPT