FAIR ALLOCATION OF DISPUTED PROPERTIES

AuthorBiung‐Ghi Ju,Juan D. Moreno‐Ternero
DOIhttp://doi.org/10.1111/iere.12251
Published date01 November 2017
Date01 November 2017
INTERNATIONAL ECONOMIC REVIEW
Vol. 58, No. 4, November 2017
FAIR ALLOCATION OF DISPUTED PROPERTIES
BYBIUNG-GHI JUAND JUAN D. MORENO-TERNERO1
Seoul National University, Korea; Universidad Pablo de Olavide, Spain, and CORE, Universit ´
e
catholique de Louvain, Belgium
We model problems of allocating disputed properties as generalized exchange economies. Therein, agents
have preferences and claims over multiple goods, and the social endowment of each good may not be sufficient
to satisfy all individual claims. We focus on market-based allocation rules that impose a two-step procedure:
assignment of rights based on claims first and voluntary exchange based on the assigned rights afterward. We
characterize three focal egalitarian rights-assignment rules that guarantee that the allocation rules are fair.We
apply our results to problems of greenhouse gas emissions and contested water rights.
1. INTRODUCTION
Fairness and distributive justice are primary concerns in practical procedures for property
rights disputes. If a rule is not perceived as fair, its adoption might be jeopardized. Failures to
agree on a new international framework dealing with greenhouse gas (GHG) emissions after
the Kyoto protocol are a point in case. Countries at different stages of economic development
have different perceptions of fairness and support different rules. Closing the gap to reach
a final resolution is a political economy problem. However, the core issue is an ethical one,
and investigating it from the perspective of normative economics will facilitate its political
resolution.
Resolving property rights disputes usually involves three general principles, namely, equal
division,proportional division, and equal sacrice. Examples can be found in numerous insti-
tutional setups (including laws and social and religious norms) or agreed conventions (such
as court settlements for accident damages or international resolutions on environmental prob-
lems). The three principles also underlie the three prominent proposals for the allocation of
GHG emission rights.2
The normative foundation of allocation schemes, such as the above three principles, has been
a key subject in the literature of fair allocation. Nevertheless, most studies in this literature either
focus on allocating a single good (money), dismissing the issue of fair initial allocation and its
influence on the final allocation of the other goods after the subsequent interactions among
Manuscript received October 2014; revised July 2016.
1We are grateful to Masaki Aoyagi (coeditor of this journal), three anonymous referees, Younghwan In, Herv´
e
Moulin, and William Thomson for detailed comments and suggestions. We also thank Yuki Funaki, Francois
Maniquet, John Roemer, and Roberto Veneziani as well as the participants at seminars and conferences where ear-
lier versions of this article have been presented, at Albany, Alicante, Bergen, Bilbao, Brussels, Kaifeng, Lisbon,
London, Madrid, Odense, Rochester, Salamanca, Seoul, Seville, Taipei, Tokyo, and Valencia. All remaining errors are
ours. Financial supports from the National Research Foundation of Korea Grant funded by the Korean Government
(NRF-2016S1A3A2924944), from the Center for Distributive Justice, Institute of Economic Research at Seoul National
University, and from the Spanish Ministry of Economics and Competitiveness (ECO2011-22919, ECO2014-57413-P)
are gratefully acknowledged. Please address correspondence to: Biung-Ghi Ju, Department of Economics, Seoul Na-
tional University, 1 Ganwak-ro, Gwanak-gu, Seoul 08826, Korea. Phone: +82 28802879. Fax: +82 28864231. E-mail:
bgju@snu.ac.kr.
2The proposal to allocate on an “equal per capita basis” (e.g., Neumayer, 2000) corresponds to equal division, the
polluter pays principle (paraphrased as “you broke it, you fix it”; e.g., Singer, 2002) to proportional division, and the
principle of equal burden sharing (e.g., Posner and Weisbach, 2010) to equal sacrifice.
1279
C
(2017) by the Economics Department of the University of Pennsylvania and the Osaka University Institute of Social
and Economic Research Association
1280 JU AND MORENO-TERNERO
claimants (e.g., O’Neill, 1982; Thomson, 2003, 2015), or assume a fixed initial distribution of
property rights, without dispute, and investigate end-state fairness (e.g., Pazner and Schmeidler,
1974; Thomson, 2011).3Therefore, they are somewhat limited for the investigation of (end-state
and procedural) fairness in some environments with conflicting claims or property rights dispute.
We provide in this article a comprehensive framework to investigate fairness in the initial
assignment of rights on disputed properties, fairness in the transaction of rights, and fairness of
the end-state allocation as well as the implications of the three categories of fairness and their
relations. Our model is an extended model of exchange economies, the extension allowing for
conflicts over properties. More precisely, agents have preferences over a finite number of goods,
and they also have initial claims on those goods. Furthermore, the available endowment of each
good may not be sufficient to satisfy all claims; i.e., the sum of individual claims exceeds the
endowment. In other words, we consider rationing problems with multiple goods where agents
can have various homogeneous or heterogeneous preferences over those goods.4
Our model is flexible enough to accommodate a variety of real-life problems involving prop-
erty rights disputes. A running interpretation of the model is as cap-and-trade systems to deal
with GHG emissions.5For such an interpretation, agents should be considered as GHG-emitting
entities, goods as energy and money (with the latter being used to produce the former), claims
as their energy consumptions on a base year and their incomes, and the social endowment as
the targeted amount for total energy consumption, below the total energy consumption on a
base year, and the net total endowment of money after paying the cost of energy production.
Another interpretation of our model is as problems of contested water rights.6In those cases,
water supply falls short of satisfying the regular amounts of water usage by the entities who
share a water source. There are two goods: water and money. Claims consist of the amount
of water used in a base year and the monetary endowment. Here, dispute exists only over the
water rights, not over money.
Various forms of markets have been developed throughout human history. Two fundamental
elements encompassing them are private property rights and voluntary exchange.7We precisely
define in our context market-based allocation rules as those rules determined by these two
elements, formalized in our model by the consecutive procedures of rights-assignment and
voluntary exchange. Our main results characterize market-based allocation rules that lead to
fair (and efficient) end-state allocations.
End-state fairness is formalized in this context as three variants of no-envy, probably the
concept with the longest tradition in the theory of fair allocation (e.g., Foley, 1967; Kolm,
1972; Varian, 1974).8No-envy is satisfied if no agent prefers anyone else’s consumption to her
own. A parallel comparative notion of fairness, defined through interpersonal comparisons of
(absolute) sacrifices, gives rise to the notion of sacrice-no-envy. Likewise, we define relative-
no-envy through interpersonal comparison of relative sacrifices (or rewards).
The rights-assignment procedure assigns property rights by means of adjudicating claims un-
der resource constraints.9Voluntary exchange yields individually rational end-state allocations,
3There exist generalizations of the rationing model introduced by O’Neill (1982) to a multidimensional setting, but
therein, even though claims refer to multiple types of assets, the endowment to be allocated is still unidimensional (e.g.,
Ju et al., 2007).
4This is the main difference with respect to bankruptcy problems dealing with the allocation of a single good (e.g.,
Thomson, 2003, 2015) where all agents are presumed to have the same monotonic preferences over the single good.
5The term is broadly used to describe a policy that sets caps on the emissions of (GHG-emitting) entities and allows
trading in the resulting emissions allowances (e.g., Stavins, 2008).
6A different analysis of these problems is Ansink and Weikard (2009).
7For instance, as Hodgson (2008, p. 326) puts it, “Together these specifications (put forward by the Austrian school
economist Ludwig van Mises) amount to a definition of the market that embraces all forms of trade or exchange that
involve private property, defined loosely as assets under private control.” This view is also shared by Adam Smith, Karl
Marx, Friedrich Hayek, etc. (see Hodgson, 2008).
8It was also used in moral philosophy as a basic test for resource egalitarian allocations (e.g., Dworkin, 1981).
9We impose solidarity in this procedure, modeled by the combination of two axioms, known as resource monotonicity
and consistency, as suggested by Moreno-Ternero and Roemer (2006, 2012), among others.

To continue reading

Request your trial

VLEX uses login cookies to provide you with a better browsing experience. If you click on 'Accept' or continue browsing this site we consider that you accept our cookie policy. ACCEPT