DIMENSIONALITY AND DISAGREEMENT: ASYMPTOTIC BELIEF DIVERGENCE IN RESPONSE TO COMMON INFORMATION

Date01 November 2019
Published date01 November 2019
AuthorGregory Phelan,Isaac Loh
DOIhttp://doi.org/10.1111/iere.12406
INTERNATIONAL ECONOMIC REVIEW
Vol. 60, No. 4, November 2019 DOI: 10.1111/iere.12406
DIMENSIONALITY AND DISAGREEMENT: ASYMPTOTIC BELIEF DIVERGENCE
IN RESPONSE TO COMMON INFORMATION
BYISAAC LOH AND GREGORY PHELAN1
Northwestern University, U.S.A.;Williams College, U.S.A.
We provide a model of boundedly rational, multidimensional learning and characterize when beliefs will
converge to the truth. Agents maintain beliefs as marginal probabilities instead of joint probabilities, and
agents’ information is of lower dimension than the model. As a result, for some observations, agents may
face an identification problem affecting the role of data in inference. Beliefs converge to the truth when these
observations are rare, but beliefs diverge when observations presenting an identification problem are frequent.
Robustly, two agents with differing priors who observe identical, unambiguous information may disagree forever,
with stronger disagreement the more information received.
1. INTRODUCTION
People disagree and sometimes in big, persistent ways: People disagree about which poli-
cies best achieve outcomes, there is substantial disagreement among professional forecasters
and central bankers regarding outlooks for macroeconomic variables,2and many patterns in
financial markets strongly suggest investor disagreement (Hong and Stein, 2007). Furthermore,
disagreements sometimes grow as people see the same information and continue to disagree.
There is ample empirical evidence that people sometimes interpret evidence differently, whether
they are Bayesian updaters or otherwise.3And yet, in many cases disagreements do not grow,
and people appear to perceive evidence in similar ways (Gerber and Green, 1999). In this
article, we provide a model of multidimensional learning that can explain why disagreements
can persist or even grow as agents observe identical information. Specifically, an agent’s be-
liefs may differ from the true probabilities even after observing arbitrarily large amounts of
information, and what beliefs converge to may depend on an agent’s initial beliefs. As a result,
observing common information can lead to permanent divergence in beliefs given arbitrarily
small initial disagreements.
Our analysis requires two ingredients. First, agents sometimes face an identification problem
for doing inference. We consider a multidimensional learning problem in which the world
is of higher dimensionality than the signals (or information) people observe. In the sense of
Benoˆ
ıt and Dubra (2019), some signals are “equivocal,” meaning that the same signal can
Manuscript received December 2017; revised January 2019.
1We are grateful for feedback from Matthew Chao, Eddie Dekel, Yingni Guo, Asim Khwaja, Rachel Kranton, Bruce
Sacerdote, Larry Samuelson, Arunava Sen, Rakesh Vohra (the editor), and anonymous referees. Please address cor-
respondence to: Gregory Phelan, Department of Economics, Williams College, 24 Hopkins Hall Drive, Williamstown,
MA 01267. Phone: 413-597-6284. E-mail: gp4@williams.edu.
2Andrade et al. (2016) find that disagreements among FOMC members about projections for the Fed Funds Rate and
other variables are even greater than the disagreements among forecasters in the Survey of Primary Dealers. The point
is not that central bankers and professional forecasters disagree, but that there is disagreement even within category
(in which presumably there are similar information sets and objectives). Furthermore, economists rarely switch from
hawks to doves (Malmendier et al., 2017).
3For example, Hirshleifer and Teoh (2003) document how the presentation of accounting information affects its
interpretation, and Malmendier et al. (2017) show that personal experiences of inflation strongly influence the hawkish
or dovish leanings of central bankers, which is evidence that priors influence how FOMC members interpret the same
information. See Benoˆ
ıt and Dubra (2019) for a thorough discussion of the literature.
1861
C
(2019) by the Economics Department of the University of Pennsylvania and the Osaka University Institute of Social
and Economic Research Association
1862 LOH AND PHELAN
rationally be used to update beliefs in different ways depending on people’s priors. Second,
agents update beliefs about marginal probabilities, not the full joint distribution. Because of
the high dimensionality of the problem, boundedly rational agents reduce the dimensionality
of their learning problem by maintaining beliefs over marginal distributions and reconstructing
joint distributions from the marginals using a fixed correlation (namely, independence).
Our modification is driven by the observation that in multidimensional environments, main-
taining a full joint prior distribution may be cognitively taxing. Fully rational agents would use
Bayes’ rule to update the joint distribution over the full state space instead of just considering
the marginals and multiplying appropriately to form a joint distribution. Hence, beliefs about
states would rarely be independent even if the underlying states are. Indeed, developing and
maintaining a prior over the whole joint distribution of states of the world may be regarded
as extremely computationally expensive, as suggested by Kominers et al. (2018). Additionally,
Enke and Zimmermann (2017) provide strong experimental evidence that many people effec-
tively ignore the need to update correlation when updating beliefs, and this effect is driven by
complexity in the environment instead of the computational skills of the agents.
These two ingredients interact in important ways, and we discuss them in turn. First, equivocal
observations may lead to greater disagreement because agents use their current beliefs to update
marginal beliefs. How might this mechanism look in reality? Consider two examples:
(1) A liberal and a conservative are watching the news together under a conservative gov-
ernment. After several reports that the country is weakening, the liberal says, “The gov-
ernment is failing us.” The conservative, responds, “No, more evidence of the media’s
liberal bias.”
(2) Two economists, a Keynesian and a Neoclassical, are discussing the results of a recent
stimulus package. The new GDP results are sluggish. The Neoclassical says, “Goes to
show that stimulus doesn’t work.” The Keynesian replies, “Oh no, goes to show that the
economy is much worse than we thought” (perhaps later adding that the stimulus was
poorly designed).
In these cases, there are a number of underlying factors that contribute to the observed
signals, but the signals are of lower dimensionality than the world. For the liberal and the
conservative, the politics of news reflect the state of the country and how credibly that is
reported. For the economists, GDP is a function of the fundamental strength of the economy,
the effectiveness of stimulus, and potentially how well designed that stimulus was. But the
observations do not identify those underlying variables. In each case, the exact same signal is
interpreted in completely different ways, but the observers are not rejecting the information,
nor is the information ambiguous or unclear: They are simply using the evidence in different,
rational ways. Each observer uses the information to make inference about different underlying
variables. The Keynesian infers that weak GDP means something about the economy, whereas
the Neoclassical infers that weak GDP means the fiscal multiplier is low.
As we formalize below, the previous examples illustrate how agents reason when updating
marginal, not joint, probabilities. The news watchers are (together) correct that the news reports
suggest either that “country weak +media truthful”or“country strong +media biased.” But
agents updating marginal beliefs effectively consider changing only one “dimension” of their
beliefs at a time. So the liberal, believing “weak +truthful,” would compare that belief to “one-
dimensional perturbations”—namely, “strong +truthful” and “weak +biased.” The liberal
rightly concludes that these beliefs are bad explanations of the news reports and thus chooses
to stick with and even reinforce the initial belief. But the conservative, starting with different
priors, would reason in precisely the same way to reach the opposite conclusion! However, if
the two people instead considered the joint distribution, they would recognize that their beliefs
about the country and the media should be correlated: The reporting suggests “weak +true”or
strong +biased.” If they recognized this correlation and focused on only these two states, then
they would have a chance of reaching agreement.

To continue reading

Request your trial

VLEX uses login cookies to provide you with a better browsing experience. If you click on 'Accept' or continue browsing this site we consider that you accept our cookie policy. ACCEPT