The Role and Value of Coherence in Theories of Legal Reasoning

AuthorMaksymilian Del Mar
Published date01 December 2017
Date01 December 2017
DOIhttp://doi.org/10.1111/raju.12180
NOTES • DISCUSSIONS • BOOK REVIEWS
The Role and Value of Coherence
in Theories of Legal Reasoning
MAKSYMILIAN DEL MAR
1
1. Introduction
Amalia Amaya’s new book, The Tapestry of Reason (Amaya 2015), is a magisterial
work: It is thoroughly multidisciplinary, elegantly written, clearly argued, and
well-structured. It is also a one-stop-shop for anyone interested in the role of coher-
ence not only in legal reasoning, but in practical reason more generally. It should
do much for the prospects of collaboration between philosophers, psychologists,
cognitive scientists, and lawyers. It calls for and deserves a wide readership.
One of the key figures in Amaya’s treatment of coherence is Neil MacCormick.
He is not the only theorist that Amaya reads in quite some detail: Aleksander Pec-
zenik and Ronald Dworkin also receive extensive treatment (Robert Alexy receives
some attention, but less than the others). But MacCormick does hold a certain pride
of place for various reasons. One of them is that he theorised about both aspects of
coherence that Amaya is interested in, namely, coherence in reasoning about law
(i.e., normative coherence) and in reasoning about fact (i.e., narrative coherence).
Further, MacCormick was a key player in the debates over coherence in legal rea-
soning in the twentieth century—his 1984 paper on coherence (MacCormick 1984)
was influential, particularly in European legal theory;
2
he was influenced by and
1
Reader in LegalTheory, Queen Mary Universityof London.
2
Indeed, Amaya’s key example of normative coherence is the case of Sweet v. Parsley [1968] 2
All ER 337 (CCA);[1970] AC 132, [1969] 1 All ER 347 (HL), whichis taken from that 1984 paper.
MacCormick, in turn, may have gotten the example from Lyndel Prott’s (1978) paper on Josef
Esser. Esser is more important in the histories of theories of legal reasoning than he is often
given credit for—this may be because he is sometimes seen more as a comparative lawyer than
a theorist (though this, of course, belies a narrow view of what theory is or can be). Esser,
together with Cha
ım Perelman (as well as,though to a lesser extent, Julius Stone andTheodore
Viehweg), were greatly influential sources for MacCormick—e.g., in both Esser and Perelman,
he found the notion of acceptability, which was crucial for him in his understanding of
V
C2017 The Authors. Ratio Juris V
C2017 John Wiley & Sons Ltd.
Ratio Juris. Vol. 30 No. 4 December 2017 (491–506)
also in turn influenced Peczenik; he translated Alexy and was one of the first theo-
rists in the Anglo-American tradition to engage with him seriously (see Alexy 1989
and MacCormick 1983a); and he had a longstanding dialogue with the views of
Dworkin.
3
All of these debates are pertinent to anyone interested in charting the
role and value of coherence in legal reasoning.
There are also more substantive reasons to engage with Amaya’s reading of Mac-
Cormick. I intend to suggest that MacCormick had a broader reading of the role
and value of coherence than Amaya ascribes to him. However, and perhaps some-
what counter-intuitively, even though I argue that role and value was broader than
Amaya suggests, I also wish to argue that its role and value nevertheless remains
limited. Its limits, however, are set less by any (allegedly greater) role he assigns to
consequential reasoning, and more by his meta-ethical commitments, in particular
his value pluralism. Keeping in mind these limits to coherence, I will, in conclud-
ing, outline some further reasons for giving coherence an important, but still mod-
est place, in an overall theory of legal reasoning.
4
2. Amaya on MacCormick
It is important to see Amaya’s reading of MacCormick in the overall context of her
project—in particular, her positioning of coherence-based accounts of legal reason-
ing as “an appealing alternative to both formalising and sceptical approaches to
legal reasoning” (Amaya 2015, 1). This already elevates the stakes: If we cannot
make a coherence-based account work, then might we be stuck with either formal-
ism or scepticism? This is a stark way to put it, but it might already have us think-
ing whether any account of legal reasoning can be “based” on one possible form of
justification (whether coherence, or any other).
At the same time, something certainly rings true in Amaya’s (more historical)
claim that the “chief motivation driving the proposal of coherence theories of law”
was to offer “an alternative (and broader) view about the scope of reason in law
than the one endorsed by formal legal positivism” (ibid., 4).
5
Thus, whether we
speak in terms of the weak or the strong version of coherence theory—i.e., weak
when it is seen as a necessary but not sufficient condition of legal justification, and
consequential reasoning (see MacCormick 1978a, n. 104); but also more broadly, the idea that
nonlogical reasoning is nonetheless subject to rational standards: that while there may be no
inevitabilityabout the result produced by this process,there are nonetheless good, sufficient,or
plausiblereasons that can be advanced (Prott 1978,468).
3
This is a complex storyfor another day, though I refer a little more to it below.
4
There might well be other reasons for limiting the role of coherence in accounts of legal rea-
soning—both William Lucy and Grant Lamond in their pieces for thissymposium speak of the
methodological importance of engaging with the thicket of legal reasoningin practice, with all
its messiness (aresult of both institutional pressures and human imperfections). Such a method
might suggest that there are always multiple forms of justification at play in legal reasoning.
This emphasis on multiple elements at play was very much a running theme in MacCormick’s
work on legal reasoning (see also his accountof “structured pluralism”:MacCormick 1991), and
one could argue thatthis emphasis was a direct result of his method (engaging with and ration-
ally reconstructingthe detail of many cases).
5
To this one might add the motivation to offer an alternative to the limited role for reason in
sceptical legal realism—but, historically, Amaya stresses the dissatisfaction with classical legal
positivism,and this seems persuasive,though remains to be tested.
492 Maksymilian Del Mar
V
C2017 The Authors. Ratio Juris V
C2017 John Wiley & Sons Ltd. Ratio Juris, Vol. 30, No. 4

To continue reading

Request your trial

VLEX uses login cookies to provide you with a better browsing experience. If you click on 'Accept' or continue browsing this site we consider that you accept our cookie policy. ACCEPT