Schauer's Anti‐Essentialism

AuthorTorben Spaak
Date01 June 2016
Published date01 June 2016
DOIhttp://doi.org/10.1111/raju.12123
Schauer’s Anti-Essentialism
TORBEN SPAAK*
Abstract. In his new book, The Force of Law, Frederick Schauer maintains that law
has no necessary properties (a position he calls legal anti-essentialism), and that
therefore jurisprudents should not assume that an inquiry into the nature of law has
to be a search for such properties. I argue, however, that Schauer’s attempt to show
that legal anti-essentialism is a defensible position fails, because his one main argu-
ment (the cognitive science argument) is either irrelevant or else incomplete,
depending on how one understands it, and because the other main argument (the
family resemblance argument) is false.
1. Introduction
In his new book, The Force of Law (Schauer 2015), distinguished jurisprudent and
first amendment scholar Frederick Schauer investigates the role of coercion in law.
He maintains that coercion is a very important feature of law, because all known
legal orders (or legal systems) are coercive and because coercion is very likely what
actually motivates most people—officials as well as citizens—to obey the law. He
argues, as regards the question of motivation, that once we substitute a distinction
between self-motivated (or self-interested), law-motivated, and other-motivated or
morally-motivated behavior for the cruder distinction between self-interested and
law-motivated behavior employed by many scholars who have been considering
our reasons for obeying the law, we will see that it is a mistake to believe that
many people obey the law just because it is the law, and that the threat of coercion
is very likely an important motivating factor. The reason why it is important to
consider other-motivated and morally-motivated behavior is, of course, that such
conformity to legal requirements does not qualify as law-motivated obedience.
But Schauer also has important things to say about jurisprudential methodology,
maintaining as he does that jurisprudents should not follow H.L.A. Hart and others
* I would like to thank the participants inthe workshop “The Force of Law. A Workshop with
Fred Schauer” at Bocconi University, Milan on 2–3 October 2014, for helpful comments on my
presentation of the ideas in this article. I would also like to thank the participants in the
advanced seminar in practical philosophy, Uppsala University, especially Jens Johansson, for
helpful comments on an earlier version of the article, and A
˚ke Fr
andberg and Patricia Mindus
for equally helpful comments on an even earlier version of the article. Finally, I would like to
thank Robert Carroll for checking my English. As always, the responsibility for any remaining
errors and imperfections in the articlerests with the author alone.
V
C2016 The Author. Ratio Juris V
C2016 John Wiley & Sons Ltd, 9600 Garsington Road, Oxford OX4 2DQ, UK and 350 Main
Street, Malden 02148, USA.
Ratio Juris. Vol. 29 No. 2 June 2016 (182–214)
in assuming that an inquiry into the nature of law must be a search for essential
properties of law (in order to qualify as an inquiry into the nature of law), but
should instead focus on properties that are typical of law and important. He addu-
ces two distinct claims in support of this main methodological claim (MMC), as I
shall refer to it, namely, (1) that law has no essential properties, and (2) that focus-
ing on essential properties of law to the exclusion of properties that are typical of
law and important, albeit not essential, means that the theorist will run the risk of
missing out on important insights. And he adduces in turn two distinct claims in
support of claim (1), namely, (1a) that people in general think of and with concepts
not in terms of necessary and sufficient conditions for their proper application, but
in terms of central and peripheral cases, and accept that not all instances, not even
all central instances, of a concept share any one property or properties, and (1b)
that the concept of law is a family resemblance concept, or a so-called cluster
concept.
I find both (MMC) and the claims (1)–(2), including the supporting claims (1a)
and (1b), interesting and well worthy of extended discussion. Clearly, since juris-
prudents focus on the question of the nature of law, they should know how to go
about an inquiry into the nature of law, and how not to, and they should also
know why they should go about such an inquiry in the one way rather than the
other. Questions such as “What is an essential property?,” “Do we have reason to
believe that law has essential properties?,” and “Assuming that law does have
essential properties, should we focus our jurisprudential inquiries exclusively on
those properties?” should be of considerable interest to any reasonably reflective
jurisprudent.
But the role of (MMC) in Schauer’s inquiry, as distinguished from its truth or
defensibility, is also interesting, and in my view somewhat puzzling. Since no juris-
prudent in his right mind would want to deny Schauer the right to investigate the
role of coercion in law, but would probably only say that, strictly speaking, such an
inquiry does not qualify as an inquiry into the nature of law, one may wonder why
Schauer considers this question to be so important. Why does he want his investi-
gation to qualify as an inquiry into the nature of law? Why does he not just go
ahead and investigate the role of coercion in law and accept that some, perhaps
quite a few, jurisprudents will not consider such an investigation to be an inquiry
into the nature of law?
The answer to this question appears to be that Schauer wishes to undertake a
philosophical investigation (or examination) of coercion in law:
Having shed the belief of sup posing that properties t hat are not conceptually ne cessary are
of little philosophi cal or jurisprudential in terest, we are now bette r situated to think about
those pervasive aspect s of law that are ubiquitous and t ypical but not conceptuall y essen-
tial. Coercion is surel y one of those aspects, an d freed from the necessity of limiting our
examination to conceptua l essences we can recover the theoretic al and philosophical exami-
nation of coercion in law f rom the exile to which a dubio us essentialism has cast i t. (Scha-
uer 2015, 43)
I do not find this answer convincing, however. For, as Schauer (2015, 4–5) himself
notes, and as is clear from his own book, an investigation of a legal phenomenon,
such as legal coercion, may well be philosophical without amounting to an
inquiry into the natu re of law, as that enterpri se has traditionally b een conceived.
Schauer's Anti-Essentialism 183
Ratio Juris, Vol. 29, No. 2 V
C2016 The Author. Ratio Juris V
C2016 John Wiley & Sons Ltd.
Why, then, does Schauer want his philosophical investigation to qualify as an
inquiry into the nature of law? Why does he not rest content knowing that his is
a very interesting , philosophically in spired investigat ion of the role of coercio n in
law?
I shall not, however , pursue this (rather mi ld) objection to Scha uer’s analysis,
but shall focus instead on Schauer’s anti-essentialism and the above-mentioned
two claims adduced by S chauer in support of i t, namely, (1a) and (1b) , and their
relation to one another. I shall argue, more specifically, (i) that Schauer’s attempt
to show that legal anti-essentialism is a defensible position fails, because argu-
ment (1a) is either irrelevant or else incomplete, depending on how one under-
stands it, and because argument (1b) is false, since the concept of law is not a
family resemblance concept, and possibly also incoherent, (ii) that claims (1a) and
(1b) could not be true together, and (iii) that Schauer’s discussion of properties of
law in the chapter on the dif ferentiation of law i s in tension with, and mig ht even
undermine, the leg al anti-essential ism that Schauer esp ouses. I shall also a rgue
(iv) that Schauer’s legal anti-essentialism does not seem to be anti-essentialism in
the usual sense of a rejecti on of the existence of ess ential properties, b ut rather a
rejection of the pos sibility of analyzin g the concept of law in t erms of necessary
and sufficient con ditions, which is a di fferent and quite r adical view. Moreov er, I
shall argue (v) that legal anti-essentialism in Schauer’s sense is a problematic doc-
trine, because it see ms to render parts of le gal scholarship, suc h as the interesting
and valuable discipline of comparative law,
1
more or less pointl ess, and (vi) that
a jurisprudent who d espite the objectio ns set forth in this ar ticle accepts legal
anti-essentiali sm (in Schauer’s sen se) should consider modifying his approach to
the inquiry into the nature of law accordingly by giving up the method of philo-
sophical analysis and trying instead either the method of explication or the
method of the ideal-type. Finally, I shall argue (vii) that we do not have to go all
the way back to the time of Bentham and Austin to find a prominent jurisprudent
who puts coercion at t he center of law, but can fi nd a much more recent jur ispru-
dent who does precisely that, namely Scandinavian realist Karl Olivecrona, and
(viii) that a compari son of Schauer’s and Ol ivecrona’s account s of legal coercion
makes it clear that th ese accounts treat ve ry different quest ions and differ quite a
bit in general, and t hat the main reason wh y this is so is that the y differ in their
understanding of what an inquiry into the nature of law is.
I begin, however, by considering the structure of Schauer’s argumentation
(Section 2) and by saying a few words about how I understand the method of
philosophical analysis, which Schauer objects to (Section 3). Having done that, I
consider the claims (1a) and (1b) in more detail, including the logical relation
between the two claims (Sections 4–8), discuss rather briefly two alternative meth-
ods of jurisprudential inquiry, namely the method of explication and the method
of the ideal-type (Section 9), and identify a tension, perhaps even a contradiction,
in Schauer’s discussion of (what Schauer refers to as) the differentiation of law
(Section 10). The article concludes, in an attempt to place Schauer’s investigation in
a larger context, with a brief consideration of Karl Olivecrona’s thoughts on legal
coercion (Section 11).
1
For a valuabletreatise on comparative law, see Zweigertand K
otz (1998).
184 Torben Spaak
V
C2016 The Author. Ratio Juris V
C2016 John Wiley & Sons Ltd. Ratio Juris, Vol. 29, No. 2

To continue reading

Request your trial

VLEX uses login cookies to provide you with a better browsing experience. If you click on 'Accept' or continue browsing this site we consider that you accept our cookie policy. ACCEPT