Realism about the Nature of Law

DOIhttp://doi.org/10.1111/raju.12073
Date01 March 2017
Published date01 March 2017
AuthorTorben Spaak
Realism about the Nature of Law
TORBEN SPAAK*
Abstract. Legal realism comes in two main versions, namely American legal realism
and Scandinavian legal realism. In this article, I shall be concerned with the
Scandinavian realists, who were naturalists and non-cognitivists, and who main-
tained that conceptual analysis (in a fairly broad sense) is a central task of legal
philosophers, and that such analysis must proceed in a naturalist, anti-
metaphysical spirit. Specifically, I want to consider the commitment to ontological
naturalism and non-cognitivism on the part of the Scandinavians and its implica-
tions for their view of the nature of law. I argue (i) that the Scandinavians differ
from legal positivists in that they reject the idea that there are legal relations, that
is, legal entities and properties, and to varying degrees defend the view that law
is a matter of human behavior rather than legal norms, and (ii) that they do not and
cannot accept the idea that there is a ‘world of the ought’ in Kelsen’s sense. I also
argue, more specifically, (iii) that the objection to non-naturalist theories raised by
the Scandinavians—that there is and can be no connection between the higher
realm of norms and values (the ‘world of the ought’) and the world of time and
space—is convincing, and (iv) that Kelsen’s introduction of a so-called modally
indifferent substrate does nothing to undermine this objection. In addition, I argue
(v) that the Scandinavians can account for the existence of legal relations that do not
presuppose the existence of morally binding legal norms by embracing conven-
tionalism about the existence of the sources of law, while pointing out that in doing
so they would also be abandoning their legal realism for legal positivism. Finally,
I argue (vi) that the implications for legal scholarship of the realist emphasis on
human behavior instead of legal norms is not well explained by the realists and
appear to amount to little more than a preference for teleological interpretation of
legal norms.
1. Introduction
Legal realism comes in two main versions, namely American legal realism and
Scandinavian legal realism. Both versions flourished in the 1930s and the 1940s.
* Professor of Jurisprudence, Department of Law, Uppsala University. I would like to thank
the participants in the advanced seminar in practical philosophy, Department of Philosophy,
Uppsala University for helpful comments on the article. I would also like to thank Åke
Frändberg, Thomas Mautner, and Patricia Mindus for helpful comments on an earlier version
of the article, Brian Bix, Erik Carlsson, Michael Steven Green, and Jaap Hage for helpful
Ratio Juris. Vol. •• No. •• •• 2015 (••–••)
© 2015 The Author. Ratio Juris © 2015 John Wiley& Sons Ltd, 9600 Garsington Road, Oxford OX4 2DQ, UK and 350 Main
Street, Malden 02148, USA.
THE NOTEBOOK CORNER
V
C2016 The Author. Ratio Juris V
C2016 John Wiley & Sons Ltd, 9600 Garsington Road, Oxford OX4 2DQ, UK and 350 Main
Street, Malden 02148, USA.
Ratio Juris. Vol. 30 No. 1 March 2017 (75–104)
But in the United States, legal realism disappeared from the forefront of legal
thinking in the 1950’s and 1960’s and was succeeded in the 1970’s and the 1980’s
primarily by the so-called Critical Legal Studies movement. And in Scandinavia,
legal realism more or less disappeared from the scene at the same time, although
its leading exponents—Alf Ross and Karl Olivecrona—continued to write in a
realist spirit about jurisprudential matters well into the 1970s. The younger gen-
erations of Scandinavian jurisprudents have not, however, been willing to take up
the mantle of the realists, although some, such as Bindreiter (forthcoming), Eng
(2007, 275–314), Mindus (2009), and Spaak (2009b, 2009c, 2011, 2013, 2014) have
written appreciatively about them. Indeed, in the past 30–40 years the teachings of
Scandinavian realists have evoked more interest in Southern Europe that in the
Nordic countries, especially in Italy. Enrico Pattaro’s writings (1972, 1980, 2007,
2009, 2010), in particular, come to mind here.1
The Scandinavian realists were naturalists and non-cognitivists,2who maintained
that conceptual analysis (in a fairly broad sense) is a central task of legal philoso-
phers, and that such analysis must proceed in a naturalist, anti-metaphysical spirit.
Indeed, I have argued elsewhere (Spaak 2009c) that the realism espoused by the
Americans and the Scandinavians alike is to be understood as a commitment to
naturalism, conceived as the ontological claim that everything is composed of
natural entities whose properties determine all the properties of that which exists,
or as the methodological (or epistemological) claim that the methods of justification
and explanation in philosophy must be continuous with those in the sciences, or as
the semantic claim that philosophically acceptable concepts must be analyzable in
terms of natural entities or properties.3
In this article, I wish to consider the commitment to ontological naturalism and
non-cognitivism on the part of the Scandinavian realists and its implications for
their view of the nature of law. I argue (i) that the Scandinavians differ from legal
positivists in that they reject the idea that there are legal relations, that is, legal
entities and properties, and to varying degrees defend the view that law is a matter
of human behavior rather than legal norms, and (ii) that they cannot and do not
accept the idea that there is a ‘world of the ought’ in Kelsen’s sense. I also argue,
more specifically, (iii) that the objection to non-naturalist theories raised by the
Scandinavians—that there is and can be no connection between the higher realm of
norms and values (the ‘world of the ought’) and the world of time and space—is
comments on Section 8, Håkan Andersson for helpful comments on Section 9, and Sven Ove
Hansson for discussing with me various philosophical questions that come up in this article.
In addition, I would like to thank the participants in the conference “New Frontiers of Legal
Realism: American, Scandinavian, European, Global” at the University of Copenhagen 29-30
May 2012—especially Jes Bjarup and Brian Leiter—for helpful comments on my presentation
of the main ideas in the article. Finally, I would like to thank Robert Carroll for checking my
English.
1On the reception of the legal philosophy of the Scandinavians in the Latin world, see Faralli
1999.
2As we shall see in Section 4, the early Olivecrona appears to have embraced at times an
error-theoretical analysis of moral and legal judgments. On this, see Spaak 2009c, 252–5.
3Leiter (2007) has argued that the American realists were methodological naturalists, who
were concerned solely with the study of adjudication. This sounds right to me. I review
Leiter’s book in Spaak (2008).
2Torben Spaak
© 2015 The Author. Ratio Juris © 2015 John Wiley & Sons Ltd. Ratio Juris, Vol. ••, No. ••
the mantle of the realists, although some, such as Bindreiter (2016), Eng
76 Torben Spaak
V
C2016 The Author. Ratio Juris V
C2016 John Wiley & Sons Ltd. Ratio Juris, Vol. 30, No. 1

To continue reading

Request your trial

VLEX uses login cookies to provide you with a better browsing experience. If you click on 'Accept' or continue browsing this site we consider that you accept our cookie policy. ACCEPT