Raz on Rights: Human Rights, Fundamental Rights, and Balancing

DOIhttp://doi.org/10.1111/raju.12156
AuthorAleardo Zanghellini
Published date01 March 2017
Date01 March 2017
Raz on Rights: Human Rights,
Fundamental Rights, and Balancing
ALEARDO ZANGHELLINI*
Abstract. After clarifying the outlines of Raz’s interest theory of rights and its rela-
tionship to aspects of the principles theory of rights, I consider how his recent obser-
vations on human rights manage to fit (or fail to fit) into the interest theory. I then
address two questions. First, I elaborate on Raz’s definition of morally fundamental
rights, arguing that he is right in claiming that there are no such rights. I then show
that the interest theory accommodates the notion that rights may take qualitative
precedence over conflicting considerations—a question that has become increasingly
relevant in light of recent writing on rights.
1. Introduction
This article has the twofold aim of showing that the explanatory power of Raz’s
interest theory of rights (ITR) is undiminished, but that some aspects of the theory
call for clarification and elaboration. I begin by sketching the outlines of the theory
and show how it relates to and illuminates some aspects of the principles theory of
constitutional rights. Although the ITR applies to all rights, debates about rights
tend to foreground our important rights. Since it is often assumed that these largely
coincide with those listed in human rights documents, I will review some of the
points Raz makes on human rights. I will show that Raz’s aims and methodology
in developing a theory of human rights practice diverge from those that informed
his formulation of the ITR. I shall then discuss those rights that have a stronger
claim to being considered our most important rights: morally fundamental rights.
Raz’s definition of morally fundamental rights as self-grounding rights is conceptu-
ally unexceptionable. However, I will try to substantiate Raz’s recent claim that
there are probably no such rights. I will then turn to work that emphasises
“qualitative” rather than “quantitative” methods of resolving conflicts involving
rights. I will argue that Raz’s ITR accommodates, both logically and terminologi-
cally, the idea that sometimes rights take qualitative precedence over conflicting
considerations.
* Professor of Lawand Social Theory, University of Reading. Many thanks to Denise Meyerson
for her comments on an earlydraft, to Stuart Lakin for our discussions on balancing, and to the
anonymousreferees for their helpful feedback.
V
C2017 The Author. Ratio Juris V
C2017 John Wiley & Sons Ltd, 9600 Garsington Road, Oxford OX4 2DQ, UK and 350 Main
Street, Malden 02148, USA.
Ratio Juris. Vol. 30 No. 1 March 2017 (25–40)
2. The ITR and the Principles Theory
Raz’s ITR is offered as a philosophical definition of rights, or an analysis of the con-
cept of right as used in “legal, political, and moral writing and discourse” (Raz
1986, 165). It aims to apply to all rights—whether important or not, and whether
moral or legal (Raz 1984a).
According to Raz, individual interests are grounds for rights, and rights are
grounds for duties, duties being peremptory reasons for action. A right exists only
if an interest of the right-holder—i.e., an aspect of her well-being—is of sufficient
importance to hold others to be under a duty (Raz 1984b, 195–6). Thus, although
rights are not the only grounds of duties, to each right corresponds at least one
duty. Frequently, however, to a right correspond several duties and the duties are
lesser than the duty to secure the object of the right (ibid., 199). For example, my
right to be a parent may ground a duty in third parties not to stop me from repro-
ducing, but it does not require that I be secured a child.
In order for an individual interest to successfully ground a right, the reasons for
action prompted by the importance of that interest must not be nullified by counter-
considerations. Raz puts it in terms of a judgement about the importance of that
individual interest relative to the importance of any relevant counter-consideration:
Where the conflicting considerations altogether outweigh the interest of the would-be right-
holder [...], then there is no right. Where the conflicting considerations override those on
which the right is based on some but not all occasions, the general coreright exists but the con-
flicting considerations may show thatsome of its possible derivations do not.(Raz 1984b, 211)
This passage also points to an important element in the structure of rights—the fact
that one can think of individual interests as grounding core rights from which further,
more specific rights can be derived (ibid., 197–9). Although Raz does not spe ll this
out, derivative rights can be stated at different levels of specificity. Thus, the core
right to be a parent grounds a more specific right to apply for adoption. This right—
call it an “intermediate right”—may in turn ground a right to a change in policies
which unjustifiably prevent certain classes of peo ple from applying for ado ption.
One question is to what extent the distinction between core rights and derivative
rights maps onto the differentiation between prima facie and definitive rights
developed by Alexy (2002), whose principles theory of constitutional rights has
become increasingly influential. For Alexy rights can take either the form of princi-
ples (ibid., 60), that is, “norms which require that something be realised to the
greatest extent possible, given the legal and factual possibilities” (ibid., 47) or rules,
that is, “decisions about what is to happen within the realm of the legally and fac-
tually possible” (ibid., 57). Generally (but not invariably) rights as declared in con-
stitutions take the form of principles. Principles can and do conflict; and they are
general, in the sense that “they have not been related to the possibilities of the fac-
tual and normative world” (ibid., 60). As such, for adjudicators a principle is a rea-
son for declaring no more than a prima facie right in the person who invokes it.
Conflicts between principles and between the concrete prima facie “ought” state-
ments that they justify (including prima facie rights)
1
are definitively resolved only
1
Not all prima facie “ought” statements justified by principles are reducible to individual
rights.
26 Aleardo Zanghellini
V
C2017 The Author. Ratio Juris V
C2017 John Wiley & Sons Ltd. Ratio Juris, Vol. 30, No. 1

To continue reading

Request your trial

VLEX uses login cookies to provide you with a better browsing experience. If you click on 'Accept' or continue browsing this site we consider that you accept our cookie policy. ACCEPT