Public Responsibilities for Electoral Fraud Beyond Correlative Rights and Duties

AuthorLeon Trakman
PositionUNSW Professor of Law and Former Dean of the Law Faculty, University of New South Wales, Sydney (Australia)
Pages17-32
Leon E Trakman, ‘Public Responsibilities for Electoral Fraud Beyond Correlative
Rights and Duties’ (2015) 31(81) Utrecht Journal of International and European
Law 17, DOI: http://dx.doi.org/10.5334/ujiel.de
RESEARCH ARTICLE
Public Responsibilities for Electoral Fraud Beyond
Correlative Rights and Duties
Leon E Trakman*
This article develops the notion that a government has a public responsibility to prevent elec-
toral fraud in a way that extends beyond the protections conferred by an electorate’s directly
correlative right to voting freedom. Focusing on electoral freedom and voter fraud in electoral
systems, it presents theoretical arguments for holding governments responsible arising from
the incomplete or unclear nature of juristic rights, powers, and duties. It holds that such public
responsibilities are functionally necessary, in the interests of a truly inclusive participatory
democracy. The article uses illustrations of fair elections globally, and in the United States
in particular, including the divided 2014 US Supreme Court decision,
US v. Texas
, in which the
majority denied the right to vote to prisoners and parolees who are disproportionately repre-
sented by ethnic minorities.
Keywords: Rights; Responsibilities; Governments; Courts; Social justice; Voting rights;
International human rights
I. Introduction
This article extends the arguments initiated in the book, Rights and Responsibilities,1 to the responsibility of
federal and state governments to protect the important political interests of citizens as individuals, or as a
collective whole, from acts of political corruption as illustrated by election fraud.2 Election fraud, as a threat
to fair elections, serves as a useful illustration of the need for public responsibilities. In the absence of an
express correlative right of legal duties imposed on governments and an express correlative right of voters
to be protected from such fraud, public responsibility provides more robust legal protection of the political
interests of a voting citizenry. This article challenges the conception of correlative jural relations popularised
by Hohfeld a century ago, that a person, including a government, is subject to a duty only if another, citizen
or the citizenry as a whole, has a correlative right by which to enforce that duty.3 It argues that this under-
standing of rights and duties is unduly restrictive because it fails to recognise important public interests,
* UNSW Professor of Law and Former Dean of the Law Faculty, University of New South Wales, Sydney (Australia).
1
Leon E Trakman and Sean Gatien, Rights and Responsibilities (University of Toronto Press 1999).
2
Insofar as democratic states conceivably ever enjoyed sovereignty that was absolute, inalienable and indivisible, that sovereignty
relates to relations between and among states, including on behalf of the citizens of that state who are part of its sovereignty. To
conceive of that sovereignty as vested in governments themselves, other than in a representative capacity, is to extend an absolute
conception of sovereignty to governments internally contrary to the tenets of a liberal democracy, not least of all, the individual
liberty of that state’s citizens not to be subjugated by that state. Second, even the conception of a sovereign state is suspect insofar
as governments, in representing states including their citizens, alienate and divide that sovereignty, such as treaty, statute or abdi-
cation, internationally, regionally and internally among organs of government. Third, and consequentially, governmental author-
ity is necessarily more limited than state sovereignty. For alternative conceptions of sovereignty, see generally, Charles Sampford
and Ramesh Thakur, Re-envisioning Sovereignty: The End of Westphalia (Ashgate 2008); Jean Cohen, Globalization and Sovereignty
(CUP 2012).
3
Wesley N Hohfeld, ‘Some Fundamental Legal Concepts as Applied in Judicial Reasoning’ (1913) 23 Yale LJ 16; Wesley N Hohfeld,
‘Fundamental Legal Conceptions as Applied in Judicial Reasoning’ (1917) 26 Yale LJ 710. See further Wilfrid E Rumble (ed), Austin:
The Province of Jurisprudence Determined (CUP 1995) 36.
UTRECHT JOURN
AL OF
INTERNATIONAL AND EUROPEAN LAW
Public Responsibilities for Electoral Fraud Beyond Correlative Rights and Duties18
such as voting integrity, that are not always protected by correlative rights. In particular, this article raises
relevant legal and philosophical considerations in determining circumstances in which governments have
affirmative responsibilities to redress perceived public wrongs, such as voter fraud, beyond their duties cor-
relative to citizens’ rights.
The pressing need for delineating circumstances where governmental responsibility should be invoked
is exemplified by the failure of governments, even those with long traditions of democracy, to provide a
sufficient remedy to redress electoral fraud. The current study illustrates how the theory of responsibility
developed in the author’s prior studies can apply to the public responsibilities of government, corporations
and individuals for free and fair elections.4
This article proposes that such an approach will benefit from greater definition, particularly in reference
to subjecting respective rights and duties to substantive principles of fairness. The author proposes that gov-
ernmental responsibility for electoral fraud, arguably, should not restricted to acts which are per se illegal,
but extend to acts which are morally unacceptable in undermining the spirit of electoral laws, and arguably,
violating the principles of democratic governance.5 Effectively, public responsibilities are needed where gov-
ernance duties are absent, incompletely articulated, or difficult to enforce.
This article discusses the extent to which governments exercise those responsibilities in fact, and how
citizens can redress lapses in such exercise, beyond their rights to vote against allegedly infracting govern-
ments. The examples are drawn primarily from election irregularities in the United States.
Such responsibilities are increasingly essential if governments are to be accountable to their citizens, and
if substantive justice is truly at the core of governance in a modern participatory democracy. As an illustra-
tion, the author recommends that, in delineating the content of governmental responsibility, the effect of
actions arising from the exercise of responsibility must be balanced so as to avoid having a disproportion-
ately discriminatory effect on minority voters.
II. The Problem Stated
The conceptual case for restricting governments’ public responsibilities for electoral irregularities is that
governments should only be subject to duties that are correlative to the electorate’s rights. If an electorate
has no right to require its government to act, then that government has no duty to act. The same reasoning
applies to candidates seeking public office and contributors to political campaigns. Those candidates and
contributors should not be subject to duties beyond the correlative rights of the electorate.6
Take the following three-part example. Electoral Candidate X argues that he or she is not subject to a for-
mal duty to refrain from engaging in racist or sexist speech in his or her electioneering campaign due to his
or her constitutional right to freedom of expression under the 14th Amendment.7 Corporation Y contends
that it is not subject to a duty to limit its contributions to a political party because it has not violated any
election law, just as it has not violated any environmental duty not to pollute the environment.8 Government
Z asserts that it is under no duty to redress such electoral irregularities in the absence of a correlative right
requiring that it do so. In effect, Individual X, Corporation Y, and Government Z all contend that they are
not responsible for their electoral practices, beyond their formal legal duties. They argue that, requiring
otherwise, would subject them to uncertainty as to the scope and legal consequences of their actions, not-
withstanding any contrary public interest in the integrity of the electoral process.
As a result, Citizen A’s voting right is tenuously protected against anyone who would violate it. A may have
no right against X, Y and Z if they do not owe A any legal duty.9 According to this juristic conception of law,
4
Trakman and Gatien (n 1).
5
See generally, Michael Alvarez and others, Election Fraud: Detecting and Deterring Electoral Manipulation (Brookings Institution
Press 2008); Mikhail G Myagkov and others, The Forensics of Election Fraud: Russia and Ukraine (CUP 2009).
6
This conception of correlative rights and duties is ascribed to Hohfeld. See further (n 3), (n 45), (n 67) and (n 71).
7
On free speech rights in elections, see Brandon S Boulter, ‘Expensive Speech: Citizens United V. FEC and the Free Speech Rights of
Tax-Exempt Religious Organizations’ (2010) BYU L Rev 2243.
8
On the reluctance of corporations to assume social responsibility for the exercise of rights, beyond those to which they are subject
to clearly defined duties, see John M Conley and Cynthia A Williams, ‘Engage, Embed, and Embellish: Theory versus Practice in the
Corporate Social Responsibility Movement’ (2005) 30 J Corp L 1. See generally, Christine Parker,Meta-Regulation: Legal Account-
ability for Corporate Social Responsibility’, in Doreen McBarnet, Aurora Voiculescu and Tom Campbell (eds), The New Corporate
Accountability: Corporate Social Responsibility and the Law (CUP 2007) 207; Radu Mareș, The Dynamics of Corporate Social Respon-
sibilities (Martinus Nijhoff Publishers 2008).
9
See further (n 24).

To continue reading

Request your trial

VLEX uses login cookies to provide you with a better browsing experience. If you click on 'Accept' or continue browsing this site we consider that you accept our cookie policy. ACCEPT