Political Constitutionalism and the Question of Constitution‐Making

Date01 September 2014
AuthorMarco Goldoni
DOIhttp://doi.org/10.1111/raju.12050
Published date01 September 2014
Political Constitutionalism and the
Question of Constitution-Making
MARCO GOLDONI
Abstract. The debate on political constitutionalism has entirely neglected the
constitution-making dimension. This is probably due to the fact that constitution-
making usually brings with it undesirable outcomes such as the entrenchment of
rights or structures. These outcomes do not respect reasonable disagreement
among citizens because they violate the only fair system for settling disagree-
ment: majority rule and equal voting rights. This article argues that political
constitutionalists may regret the absence of any claim about constitution-making.
Either they are overlooking certain problems inherent to the electoral process
that is supposed to tackle disagreement or, even worse, they are downplaying
the entrenching effect of ordinary political processes by ignoring the redemptive
properties of constituent power. In both cases, their claims undermine the politi-
cal dimension of constitutionalism.
Political constitutionalism (e.g., Griffith 1979; Waldron 1999; Tomkins 2005;
Bellamy 2007) as a theory in which the principle of political equality plays a
central role can be praised for several reasons. From the appraisal of representa-
tive democracy to the focus on the importance of respect for disagreement,
political constitutionalism has been able to pinpoint many deficiencies in con-
temporary constitutional theory. A considerable amount of attention has been
paid to the attack by political constitutionalists on the legitimacy of judicial
review (see Waldron 2006; Fallon 2008; Kavanagh 2009; Craig 2011). However,
this is not the only controversial claim coming from political constitutionalists.
The aim of this article is to stress the absence of any serious reflection on
constitution-making1in the works of political constitutionalists, and to show why
this rejection is regrettable even from the internal point of view of the theory.
This absence is not really surprising, given that for these theorists, a political
constitution is equivalent to the continuous making of a constitution (Gee and
1Constitution-making is used in this paper as a concept for any kind of constitution writing
or transformation. As a result, it encompasses constitution enactment and constitutional
amendments. Constitution-making does not necessarily entail entrenchment, but in this article
only constitution-making leading to some kind of constitutional entrenchment will be
considered.
bs_bs_banner
Ratio Juris. Vol. 27 No. 3 September 2014 (387–408)
© 2014 The Author. Ratio Juris © 2014 John Wiley& Sons Ltd, 9600 Garsington Road, Oxford OX4 2DQ, UK and 350 Main
Street, Malden 02148, USA.
Webber 2010). Political constitutionalists support the idea that any conception of
higher law is illegitimate because it either implies natural law or assumes that
there are higher and lower forms of politics. In terms of the vexed question of
the relation between constitutionalism and democracy, this means that constitu-
tional entrenchment as the outcome of constitution-making is illegitimate, both in
its absolute and relative versions.2As a result, from a political constitutionalist
perspective it does not make sense to think of different levels of constitution-
making, such as enacting, transforming or amending a constitution (cf. Arato
2011). Given the centrality of politics in this theory, this may appear to be a
rather perplexing absence. In fact, in many instances, constitution-making is
deemed to be one of the most intense political activities (Elazar 1986). As Arendt
(1990, 141) has reminded us, at least from the eighteenth century onwards, there
was a revolutionary tradition highly appreciative of political participation under-
lying many written constitutions, and constitution-making came to be under-
stood as the product of these periods of great political freedom.
The gist of the argument outlined in this article is that the omission of any
consideration of the added value of constitution-making, at least in certain circum-
stances, is not a casual outcome, but a side-effect of a certain, perhaps reductive,
conception of politics and, more generally, of a partial reading of the main
principles of constitutionalism. This article intends to stress two points, both related
to how political equality is understood by political constitutionalism. The first is
that the critique of any kind of constitutional law as higher law does not hold up
to closer scrutiny; the second is that the praise of the adaptability of the political
constitution to new political or social circumstances is highly exaggerated. From
this point of view, the main lesson of political constitutionalism would be greatly
enhanced if constituent power were to be taken into account. Both critiques point
to the absence of a reflection on the idea of constitutional identity in the scholarly
work on political constitutionalism (Jacobsohn 2010).
1. The Core of the Normative Case for Political Constitutionalism:
Political Equality
As a constitutional theory, political constitutionalism is comprised mainly of three
tenets. The first states that a legitimate constitutional order should be based on the
principle of political equality. Starting from the recognition of the two fundamental
conditions of politics, that is, an irreducible plurality of opinions on common
collective problems and the need to find a solution to deal with them (Waldron
1999, 107–9; Weale 1999, 8–12), the conclusion one can draw is that the only
principle that can secure equal respect among the people is political equality. Equal
concern entails that the interests of all citizens should be equally promoted. One
may interpret this condition in output terms (Scharpf 1999, 10–2), considering the
political process only instrumentally as a means to achieve certain outcomes. But
political constitutionalists also believe that reasonable disagreement applies to the
evaluation of outcomes (Christiano 1996; Waldron 1999). For this reason, equal
concern involves according equal weight to their opinions and beliefs. In this
2For different kinds of entrenchment, see Albert 2009, 678–97.
388 Marco Goldoni
© 2014 The Author. Ratio Juris © 2014 John Wiley & Sons Ltd. Ratio Juris, Vol. 27, No. 3

To continue reading

Request your trial

VLEX uses login cookies to provide you with a better browsing experience. If you click on 'Accept' or continue browsing this site we consider that you accept our cookie policy. ACCEPT