Machiavelli, Guicciardini and the “Governo Largo”

DOIhttp://doi.org/10.1111/raju.12081
Date01 June 2015
Published date01 June 2015
AuthorCesare Pinelli
Machiavelli, Guicciardini
and the “Governo Largo”
CESARE PINELLI
Abstract. Niccolò Machiavelli’s support for what he calls governo largo, or popular
government, is usually contrasted with the diffidence towards it of Francesco
Guicciardini, the Florentine aristocrat. The article argues that both these authors
grounded their vision on Polybius’ theory of “mixed government,” though adapt-
ing it in different directions. In examining this difference, the article reaches the
conclusion that it concerns far less the degree of popular participation in political
decision-making and government than the value that Machiavelli and Guicciardini
respectively ascribe to it in comparison with that of safety-liberty (or legal cer-
tainty). In this respect, their theories may be viewed as anticipating the tensions
between democracy and the rule of law, the co-presence of which provides the
essential foundation of the structure of present-day constitutional democracies.
1.
After the Medici family were first thrown out of Florence in 1494, a Great Council
was established. Comprising approximately 3,000 representatives of the aristocracy
and the middle classes, the Great Council rapidly became the emblem of a “governo
largo,” i.e., a “broad” or a “popular” government. It was fiercely contested by the
aristocracy, or “ottimati,” who championed the return of a “governo stretto” (or
“narrow government”) under their control (Gilbert 1970, 60). Florence had more
than 100,000 inhabitants, so we should not project onto the Great Council the idea
of political egalitarianism that we associate with the concept of democracy (Gilbert
1977, 73). Rather, the “broad/narrow” dichotomy signified the inclusion or exclu-
sion from the city government of what was referred to at the time as “the people.”
This fact is confirmed by the distinction current at the time between two ways
of consulting citizens about decisions. “Pratiche larghe” (broad-based consultative
meetings) were attended by between 100 and 500 citizens representing every
district of Florence in equal measure, whereas “pratiche strette” (“narrow” meetings)
convened between 10 and 20 members and were reserved for representatives of the
richest and most powerful families. Those in favour of the 1494 Constitution soon
clashed with the aristocracy over this as well (Gilbert 1977, 72).
The contrast between “governo largo” and “governo stretto” was also used to refer
to the choice between drawing lots and elections for the purposes of conferring
government appointments. The nobles, who had been able to manipulate the
bs_bs_banner
Ratio Juris. Vol. 28 No. 2 June 2015 (267–85)
© 2015 The Author. Ratio Juris © 2015 John Wiley& Sons Ltd, 9600 Garsington Road, Oxford OX4 2DQ, UK and 350 Main
Street, Malden 02148, USA.
drawing of lots in the past, feared that the decision to have recourse to elections to
the Great Council would put them at a disadvantage. This was until they realised
that drawing lots allowed members of the middle classes to gain access to office by
means of a wider field of candidates, whereas elections resulted in the appointment
of well-known names, generally aristocrats (Gilbert 1970, 55). At this point drawing
lots came to be systematically associated with a governo largo and elections with a
governo stretto (Manin 2010, 69).
The preference for popular government of Niccolò Machiavelli (who was then
Chancellery Secretary) has from time immemorial been contrasted with the diffi-
dence towards it by Francesco Guicciardini, who “had the family pride of a
Florentine aristocrat” (Gilbert 1970, 236). However, if we shift the comparative
focus onto the different interpretations of “governo largo” just indicated and, above
all, attempt such a comparison from a constitutionalist perspective, I believe there
are grounds for revisiting this contrast.
A useful starting point is to be found in an examination of the two authors’
approaches to the subject of forms of government. This is in order to identify the
lowest common denominator that might make the comparison plausible. I will then
consider the instances when the two writers use the term “governo largo” and the
nature of the arguments supporting their respective theses, according to whether it
was the Roman republic or the Florence of the time that was the issue under
discussion. On this basis, I propose to show how their positions on the concept of
governo largo may correspond to competing visions of a constitutional order and,
albeit in embryonic form, represent some of the structural dilemmas facing con-
temporary constitutionalism. The intention is to rule out an over-simplistic exploi-
tation of the classical authors, and Machiavelli in particular, that is still found in
contemporary debates.
2.
In the wealth of literature dedicated to Machiavelli and Guicciardini, the question
of forms of government is one of the subjects attracting the greatest attention. It is
also one of the most controversial, given the historical and theoretical aspects
discernible in the two authors’ most important works. This is only of interest to us
here for the purpose of ascertaining whether their positions regarding a governo
largo stem from premises that are sufficiently similar to permit a subsequent
comparison. This condition is both necessary and sufficient for comparative pur-
poses and, in searching for it, I will allow the two authors to speak for themselves
by citing well-known, fundamental passages. Thus, after declaring his desire “to
represent things as they are in real truth, rather than as they are imagined,”
Machiavelli warns that:
[m]any have dreamed up republics and principalities which have never in truth been known
to exist; the gulf between how one should live and how one does live is so wide that a man
who neglects what is actually done for what should be done learns the way to self-destruction
rather than self-preservation. The fact is that a man who wants to act virtuously in every way
necessarily comes to grief among so many who are not virtuous. (Machiavelli 1984, 59)
The allusion to the humanist rhetoricians who dreamed up republics and princi-
palities “never known to exist” confirms, by counterpoint, that the writer is looking
268 Cesare Pinelli
© 2015 The Author. Ratio Juris © 2015 John Wiley & Sons Ltd. Ratio Juris, Vol. 28, No. 2

To continue reading

Request your trial

VLEX uses login cookies to provide you with a better browsing experience. If you click on 'Accept' or continue browsing this site we consider that you accept our cookie policy. ACCEPT