Law and the Evolutionary Turn: The Relevance of Evolutionary Psychology for Legal Positivism

Published date01 September 2014
AuthorArthur Dyevre
DOIhttp://doi.org/10.1111/raju.12049
Date01 September 2014
Law and the Evolutionary Turn:
The Relevance of Evolutionary
Psychology for Legal Positivism
ARTHUR DYEVRE
Abstract. In the present essay, I consider the relevance of evolutionary psychology
(EP) for legal positivism, addressing the two main traditions in the legal positivist
family: (1) the tradition I identify with the works of Hart and Kelsen and
characterize as “normativist,” as it tries to describe law as a purely or, at least, as
an essentially normative phenomenon, while remaining true to the ideal of scien-
tific objectivity and value-neutrality; (2) the tradition I broadly refer to as “legal
realism,” which equates law with adjudication and “legal science” with the task of
explaining judicial behaviour.
1. Introduction
After the “critical legal studies” and the “law and economics” movement, “law and
evolutionary biology” seems well on its way to becoming a leading force in
American law schools, and the wave could well spill over to European law faculties
(Elliott 1996; Jones 1996, 2000, 2004, 2005; Jones and Goldsmith 2005; Zywicki 1999;
Załuski 2009). That evolutionary theory will eventually revolutionize legal thinking
may not be as obvious as the most enthusiastic advocates of the new creed would
have us believe. Still, the movement has already spawned a rapidly expanding
literature, which suggests that lawyers and legal scholars may have something
useful to learn from Darwin and his twenty-first century disciples. A brief review
of recent journal articles and monographs reveals that insofar as scholars regard
evolutionary biology as a source of potential insights for the law, it is primarily as
a source of insights for law-making or for the normative discipline of legal
philosophy. The relevance of evolutionary thinking for law is in answering ques-
tions such as “How can evolutionary biology help us design better, more efficient
legal rules?” (Jones 2000) or “What values and political philosophy can the law
effectively realize given what evolution says about human nature?”1(Załuski 2009,
1An illustration is given by Zaluski (2009, 79), who argues that the view of human nature
emerging from evolutionary theory should determine to a certain degree our choice of
political philosophy.
bs_bs_banner
Ratio Juris. Vol. 27 No. 3 September 2014 (364–86)
© 2014 The Author. Ratio Juris © 2014 John Wiley& Sons Ltd, 9600 Garsington Road, Oxford OX4 2DQ, UK and 350 Main
Street, Malden 02148, USA.
79). As these questions suggest, the approach implicit in the work of those who
purport to explore the interconnections between law and evolutionary theory is
essentially normative. Evolutionary biology is relevant to law because lawyers seek
to make the law more efficient and effective. Whether and to what extent evolu-
tionary insights could also inform positivist theories of law and positivist
approaches to the study of legal systems, on the other hand, is a question that has
not attracted much attention.2On this score, law differs from economics and other
social sciences, where the findings and methods of post-Darwinian evolutionary
theory have been mainly deployed not as tools to improve policy-making but
rather as a basis to revisit the theoretical foundations of disciplines conceived in
primarily positive terms.3
In the present essay I consider the relevance of evolutionary psychology (EP) for
positivist theories of law. Although I focus on EP because it has made the boldest
claim to re-examine the behavioural assumptions that provide the mainstay of the
modern social sciences, much of what I say is relevant for the broader debate on
the application of evolutionary approaches—of which EP is only one among several
competing research paradigms—to law and legal thinking. In my analysis I address
the two main traditions in the legal positivist family4: (1) the tradition I identify
with the works of H.L.A. Hart and Hans Kelsen and call the “normativist”
tradition, as it tries to describe law as a purely or, at least, as an essentially
normative phenomenon while remaining true to the ideal of scientific objectivity
and value-neutrality; (2) the tradition I broadly refer to as “legal realism,” which
equates law with adjudication and “legal science” with the task of explaining
judicial behaviour. On the assumption that the claims of EP are correct, I try to
2Załuski (2009, 132) touches on the issue when he notes that “legal positivism [. . .] does
not postulate an interdisciplinary approach to law”. In any case, he sees his own work
as articulating a new theoretical current alongside legal positivism, Kelsen’s pure theory of
law, natural law, legal hermeneutics, legal realism, law and economics and the Critical
Legal Studies movement rather than as a source of insights for these various strands in
legal philosophy (ibid., 132–7).
3In economics see, e.g., Pelikan (2011) and Hodgson (2002, 2004). See also the argument of
prominent evolutionary psychologists in Cosmides and Tooby (1994) and Tooby and
Cosmides (2007). For a spirited defense of the view that sociologists should pay heed to the
findings of evolutionary theory too, see Freese et al. (2003) and Lopreato and Crippen (2001).
For a similar argument in political science, see Hibbing and Smith (2007) and Somit and
Peterson (2003).
4I realise that counting legal realism as a member of the legal positivist family may seem odd.
The term “legal positivism” is itself ambiguous. Many still equate it with formalistic doctrines
according to which statutes are always clear and constitute the only valid source of law. For
this reason, legal realism, with its emphasis on judicial law-making and judicial discretion, is
sometimes viewed as a reaction against legal positivism. However, this view does not apply
for the kind of positivism advocated by Hart and Kelsen, who cannot be suspected of
embracing any form of statutory formalism. As shown by Leiter (2001), the theoretical
position articulated by Hart (1961) is not inconsistent with the research programme of
American legal realists. On the contrary, the realist project seems to presuppose a theory of
law along the lines of Hart’s. More to the point, though, what justifies my lumping together
Hart and Kelsen with legal realists (at least American ones) is that all these approaches
fundamentally treat law as a social fact, although they differ in the research question they
emphasize. I am not alone in characterizing legal realism as a branch of legal positivism; see,
e.g., Grzegorczyk et al. 1992.
Law and the Evolutionary Turn 365
© 2014 The Author. Ratio Juris © 2014 John Wiley & Sons Ltd.Ratio Juris, Vol. 27, No. 3

To continue reading

Request your trial

VLEX uses login cookies to provide you with a better browsing experience. If you click on 'Accept' or continue browsing this site we consider that you accept our cookie policy. ACCEPT