Kant's Legacy and the Idea of a Transitional Jus Cosmopoliticum

AuthorClaudio Corradetti
DOIhttp://doi.org/10.1111/raju.12116
Date01 March 2016
Published date01 March 2016
NOTES • DISCUSSIONS • BOOK REVIEWS
Kant’s Legacy and the Idea
of a Transitional Jus Cosmopoliticum
CLAUDIO CORRADETTI*
[...] just as individuals unite in a civil state, so these warring states must unite in a state of
nations, in which their conflicts will be decided in accordance with positive laws. —This,
anyway, is the decision of pure reason, and the federation of nations [V
olkerbund] proposed
by Kant for the preservation of peace is no more than an intermediary condition [...]. (Fichte
2001, 319; italics added)
1. Kant’s Cosmopolitan Rationale: A Transitional Reading
At the end of the eighteenth century, when Kant elaborated his major political writ-
ings, not many would have thought of history as a cosmopolitan project. Kant
(2009, 9–23), however, dedicated nine propositions to elucidate his views in the
“Idea for a Universal History with a Cosmopolitan Aim.” Skepticism in this respect
is referred to with the Abb
e de St. Pierre’s and Rousseau’s “ridiculed” cosmopoli-
tanism “because they believed its execution was too near” (ibid., 17), so that
“universal world history,” says Kant, should rather be understood in terms of “a
regular course of improvement of state constitutions” (ibid., 21).
1
For Kant the
* Earlier versions were presented at the Prague Conference on Philosophy and Social Science,
22–25 May 2014; at theNordic Network in Political Theory, Oslo, 2 November 2013; andat the
Conference Transitional Cosmopolitanism, Oslo, 3–4 March2014. For comments and suggestionsI
would like to thank A. Wood for guidance on crucial paragraphs, as well as F. Zaumseil,
S. Baiasu, M. Kumm,A. Ferrara, S. Langvatn, H. Williams,R. Maliks, A. Føllesdal, G. Cesarale,
and H. Pedersen. Any remaining errors are mine. Thisarticle is prepared under the auspices of
MultiRights, European Research Council Advanced Grant #269841 at the University of Oslo,
Norway.
1
On the relation between Kant’s “theoretical” and “practical” thesis of the philosophy of his-
tory that is also reflected in the role of the progression toward perpetual peace, Wood (2006,
254ff.) observes: “It is important to distinguish between two quite different (and largely inde-
pendent) thesesthat Kant maintains here. The first thesis [...] is a whollytheoretical one: under
the guidance of heuristic or regulativeprinciples of reason, we should attempt to make sense of
human history as a process involving an unconscious and unintended teleology of nature [...]
whose ends [...] also include the creation of a perfectly just civil constitution and a peaceful
internationalorder among states. [...] A second thesis[...] is a practicalor moral one: As human
V
C2016 The Author. Ratio Juris V
C2016 John Wiley & Sons Ltd, 9600 Garsington Road, Oxford OX4 2DQ, UK and 350 Main
Street, Malden 02148, USA.
Ratio Juris. Vol. 29 No. 1 March 2016 (105–121)
cosmopolitan ideal represents a long-term project. This is due to the fact that he
not only thinks that it is contradictory to “justify an offensive war” (Kant 2012a,
8:355, 103)
2
by recourse to principles of law, but also because “what applies under
natural law to human beings in the lawless condition [...] cannot also apply to
states under international right (since, as states, they already have an internal legal
constitution and have thus outgrown the coercion by which others subject them to
a broader legal constitution” (Kant 2006b, 8:355, 80). It is by attempting to solve
this conundrum that the hypothesis of a “transitional” interpretation of Kant’s cos-
mopolitanism gains legitimacy. However, even though there are already some
“transitional” interpretations of Kant, a question remains with regard to what
might have been the most legitimate transnational arena compatible with Kant’s
notion of state sovereignty.
3
In the following sections, I will therefore defend the idea that Kant’s argument
relies on a distinct view for the “transitional” character of cosmopolitan law which
defines a normative space that avoids the danger of a world state. According to
this suggested interpretation, the relation between cosmopolitan law and its institu-
tional instantiations is explained by the function the former plays as a “freedom
generating” advancement. Among those most relevant to the argument I offer here,
both Kleingeld and Brown are worth mentioning. However, my interpretation dif-
fers from theirs in important ways. Whereas Kleingeld attributes to Kant’s change
of mind the institutional shift from a weak noncoercive league to a coercive state of
states, and Brown emphasizes the practical implementation of cosmopolitan law as
a form of legal transition, I will attempt to reconstruct and explain how the multi-
ple institutional entities Kant refers to are to be considered parts of a single pattern.
This hypothesis justifies the idea of an inherent transitional character of transna-
tional improvements brought about by cosmopolitan right.
4
This is also the pattern toward the achievement of international peace as a solu-
tion to conflict through legal means. What is most important here is that such a
condition embeds not only a trajectory of progressively legally binding configura-
tions beyond the state, but also a form of synchronic transitionality whereby func-
tional differentiation does not raise uncontestable and conclusive claims of
beings, we have a dutyto work together toward devising and realizing the end of a perfect civil
constitutionadministering justice among human beings, and to this end we are also requiredto
seek an order guaranteeing peace among states [...] The first (theoretical) thesis is in no way
dependent on the second (practical or moral) thesis. [...] Yet there is one connection between
Kant’s theoretical theses about history and his practical ones. [...] The fact that, according to a
teleologicallyconceived theoretical philosophyof history, a natural purposiveness leadstoward
an ideal civilconstitution and toward perpetualpeace between nations—andeven more, the fac-
tual reasons why it does so—constitutes part of the reason why we have a moral duty to place
an ideal civilconstitution and perpetualpeace among the ends of our action.”
2
In the same paragraph Kant defines Grotius, Pufendorf, and Vattel as “sorry comforters.” On
the role that morality plays in Kant in maintaining “the possibility of peace,” see Capps 2011,
88ff.
3
Certainly Fichte in the epigraph could be mentioned as the first to suggest a “transitional”
interpretationof Kant. For contemporary approachesto Kant’s cosmopolitanism, see also Klein-
geld 2012, 7ff.,and Brown 2008, 430. For a “transitional”interpretation of Kant more focusedon
the contemporarylegal understanding,see Niesen 2014.
4
See, in particularKleingeld 2006, 7, and Brown 2008, 430ff.For the notion of Verkehr see Kant
2006c, 6:352,146.
106 Claudio Corradetti
V
C2016 The Author. Ratio Juris V
C2016 John Wiley & Sons Ltd. Ratio Juris, Vol. 29, No. 1

To continue reading

Request your trial

VLEX uses login cookies to provide you with a better browsing experience. If you click on 'Accept' or continue browsing this site we consider that you accept our cookie policy. ACCEPT