Justice and Well‐Orderedness: Saving Rawls from Luck Egalitarianism

AuthorJahel Queralt
Date01 December 2016
DOIhttp://doi.org/10.1111/raju.12146
Published date01 December 2016
Justice and Well-Orderedness: Saving
Rawls from Luck Egalitarianism
JAHEL QUERALT
1
Abstract. This paper develops a full account of Rawls’s notion of a well-ordered soci-
ety and uses it to address two luck egalitarian objections to his principles of justice.
The first is an internal criticism which claims that Rawls’s account of justice is better
captured by a responsibility-sensitive egalitarian account. The second is an external
objection according to which,regardless of the alleged inconsistency between Rawls’s
principles and his account of justice, we should reject those principles in favour of a
responsibility-sensitive criterion because it better captures our moral intuitions about
distributive justice.The argument presentedanswers both objections by defendingthe
value of well-orderedness and showing the difficulties of responsibility-sensitive egali-
tarian conceptionsin realizing this ideal.
1. Introduction
One of the main objections to Rawls’s conception of justice is that its principles are
not sensitive enough to individual choice and responsibility. This criticism was first
voiced by some libertarians but has been forcefully restated by some liberal egali-
tarians, known as luck egalitarians, who believe that the notion of responsibility
should be at the core of an egalitarian conception of distributive justice. The luck
egalitarian critique of Rawls’s proposal takes two forms. First, it is presented as an
internal objection according to which a responsibility-sensitive egalitarian criterion
is truer to Rawls’s motivation for developing an egalitarian conception of justice
than the principles defended in A Theory of Justice (Rawls 1971, 1999a). Second, the
critique is also formulated as an external objection that claims that, regardless of
the alleged inconsistency between Rawls’s principles and his motivation, we
should reject those in favour of a responsibility-sensitive criterion because it better
1
This paper was written while I was a fellow at the Centre for Advanced Studies
Justitia Amplificata in Frankfurt. Earlier versions of it were presented at the
Forschungskolleg Humanwissenschaften in Bad Homburg, the Universidad de C
ordoba
(Argentina), the Universidad de Palermo (Argentina), the Universidad Aut
onoma de Madrid,
the Universityof Girona, and the V Meetingson Ethics and Political Philosophyin Braga. I thank
these audiences and, in particular, I~
nigo Gonzalez Ricoy, Hugo Seleme, and an anonymous
reviewer forthis journal for many helpful comments.
V
C2016 The Author. Ratio JurisV
C2016 John Wiley & Sons Ltd, 9600 Garsington Road, Oxford OX4 2DQ, UK and 350 Main
Street, Malden 02148, USA.
Ratio Juris. Vol. 29 No. 4 December 2016 (519–534)
captures what egalitarian justice should be about.
2
Both versions of the critique
have received considerable attention from liberal egalitarians unsympathetic to the
luck egalitarian project. Some of them have addressed the internal objection argu-
ing that luck egalitarians have a mistaken understanding of Rawls (Freeman 2007;
Scheffler 2003), whereas others have launched a wholesale attack on luck egalitari-
anism in response to the external objection (Anderson 1999; Hinton 2001; Shiffrin
2004; Wolff 1998).
This paper seeks to make a twofold contribution to this body of work. First, it
advances an argument against the luck egalitarian objection that shows the value
of the Rawlsian notion of a well-ordered society and the difficulties luck egalitari-
anism has in realizing it. I will call this argument the well-orderedness argument.
Against the internal objection, the argument allows us to say that given that
Rawls’s concern was to identify principles for a well-ordered society, he had good
reasons for rejecting a responsibility-sensitive egalitarian criterion. In response to
the external version, it claims that the significance of well-orderedness gives us a
reason to prefer Rawls’s proposal to luck egalitarianism. Second, in presenting this
argument, the paper seeks to give a full account of the notion of a well-ordered
society, which has not received the attention that other Rawlsian concepts have
attracted.
The exposition will proceed as follows. The first section offers a brief sketch of
the debate between Rawls and luck egalitarians. The second section explains the
Rawlsian ideal of a well-ordered society and shows its desirability by pointing out
the ways in which it contributes to the achievement of three other values, namely,
stability, equal consideration to all individuals, and autonomy. The third section
looks at the requirements deriving from well-orderedness when we take into
account certain persistent facts of reality. The fourth section examines the difficul-
ties of luck egalitarian conceptions to meet these requirements, and a brief final sec-
tion concludes.
2. The Debate
As many other discussions in Anglo-American political philosophy, the recent
debate on the role of responsibility within egalitarian justice has its origins in
Rawls’s work. In A Theory of Justice he defends a conception called “democratic
equality” that is, to a significant extent, motivated by the intuition that justice
requires to mitigate the unequal effects of social and natural lotteries in people’s
lives (Rawls 1999a, 64). His proposed solution to deal with these inequalities com-
bines a system of fair equality of opportunity, which nullifies the impact of social
background in the distribution of advantages, with the difference principle, which
allows economic inequalities only to the extent that they benefit the worst-off. In
this way, the difference principle mitigates—although it does not nullify—the con-
sequences of the unequal distribution of personal resources.
3
Luck egalitarians
share Rawls’s intuition about the unfairness of social and natural inequalities but
they think his proposal falls short of realizing it because the difference principle is
2
Arneson (2008,80) clearly distinguishes betweenthe two objections.
3
This is the content of Rawls’s second principle of justice, which is subordinated to his first
principleof equal basic liberties.
520 Jahel Queralt
V
C2016 The Author. Ratio Juris V
C2016 John Wiley & Sons Ltd. Ratio Juris, Vol. 29, No. 4

To continue reading

Request your trial

VLEX uses login cookies to provide you with a better browsing experience. If you click on 'Accept' or continue browsing this site we consider that you accept our cookie policy. ACCEPT