Is there only One Correct Legal Answer to a Question of Fact? Three Talmudic Answers to a Jurisprudential Dilemma

Published date01 December 2016
AuthorMartin P. Golding,Yuval Sinai
DOIhttp://doi.org/10.1111/raju.12144
Date01 December 2016
Is there only One Correct Legal
Answer to a Question of Fact? Three
Talmudic Answers to a Jurisprudential
Dilemma
YUVAL SINAI and MARTIN P. GOLDING
Abstract. This article focuses on questions of pure fact-of-the-matter and asks
whether two omniscient judges (or jurists or scholars) may disagree over the legal
answer to a straightforward question of a matter of fact. There are approaches to
legal theory among some western and Jewish philosophers of law whereby at least
superficially it is possible that two or more contradictory legal statements regarding
a given reality can be equally correct. The article provides a critical analysis of three
different models derived from the Jewish legal literature, and reviews the contribu-
tions of Jewish sources to the understanding of the phenomenon of disagreements
concerning matters of fact.
Human reason knows a simple and indivisible truth piecemeal and through
opposing views, with the result that it never adequately measures up to it. The
weakness of human reason was evident to Cusa because its primary rule is the
principle of noncontradiction, which states that contradictories cannot be simulta-
neously true of the same object. He insisted that there is a “coincidence of
opposites” [coincidentia oppositorum] in reality, especially in the infinite God.
—Nicholas of Cusa (1401–1464), quoted in Edwards 1967, vol. 5, p. 497
1. The Dilemma
Does the principle of bivalence (the assertion that every statement is either true or
false) apply to matters of fact? The present article considers three answers to this
jurisprudential dilemma. Given that in the article we examine the legal answer (or
conclusion) to a question (or matter) of fact, we use the legal analogue of the princi-
ple of bivalence (Golding 2003), that is, the assertion that every statement of law
that can be formulated using the vocabulary of a given legal system is valid and
V
C2016 The Author. Ratio Juris V
C2016 John Wiley & Sons Ltd, 9600 Garsington Road, Oxford OX4 2DQ, UK and 350 Main
Street, Malden 02148, USA.
Ratio Juris. Vol. 29 No. 4 December 2016 (478–505)
correct or else it is invalid or incorrect. We therefore prefer to use the term correct
(or right) and valid rather than true.
It seems irrational to argue that we could have two or more contradicting state-
ments of law about a straightforward matter of fact, all of them correct and valid.
1
Nevertheless, the issue is not so simple, as we are dealing with facts in the legal
context.
Although the distinction between matters (or questions) of law and fact seems
intuitively obvious, we think it can be made more precise for the purposes of this
article, by using Hans Kelsen’s normativism (Kelsen 1967). According to Kelsen,
laws are norms and the normativity of norms is expressed by the idea that, when
properly formulated, laws tell people (primarily judges) what they ought to do, and
by extension, what they ought not to do. It seems clear that this formulation does
not apply to statements of fact. But laws and norms are often based on findings
about facts, and according to Kelsen, the facts are always judicial, as found by the
court, and not true facts in any extralegal sense. Indeed, as argued by a recent
scholar of legal epistemology, “it is crucial to see that the valid/invalid distinction
does not map neatly onto the true/false verdict dichotomy” (Laudan 2006, 13). We
settle the truth of a verdict by comparing it with the facts. By contrast, we settle the
validity of a verdict by comparing it with the evidence presented at trial, asking
whether that evidence meets the applicable standard of proof. If one were to ask a
typical lawyer whether there might be more than “one correct answer” with
respect to factual questions, the lawyer might well say something like the follow-
ing: Of course there can be. Factual “truth” in the legal context is partly con-
structed. It relies on set procedures, which might yield results different from the
actual “facts-of-the-matter.” And different procedures, or the same procedures tak-
ing different avenues, might yield different results. In any event, regardless of the
procedures employed, fallible human beings will disagree. Moreover, questions of
fact are often substantively intertwined with questions of law, so that to the same
extent that there might be more than “one correct answer” to questions of law,
there will also be more than “one correct answer” to such mixed questions of law
and fact.
The present article is based to a great extent on the important distinction
between monistic and pluralistic approaches. Many theoreticians have addressed
the following key question: Is there only one right answer to every legal question,
or are there difficult cases in which the judge has the discretion to choose between
various alternatives. A typical defender of the monistic position in law is Ronald
Dworkin, who raised a variety of arguments in support of this thesis (Dworkin
1985, 120; 1977). Ronald Dworkin is known for maintaining that there is (almost)
always a right answer to questions of law. At one point he suggested that the right
answer is the one that would be given by Hercules, a judge who has omniscient
knowledge of the law (Dworkin 1977, 105; 1986, 264). Dworkin argued that the
monist theory is valid even if we do not always know the right answer. Dworkin’s
“one right answer” thesis has been challenged by Hart and others when it comes to
questions of law. Proponents of legal pluralism adopt the opposite view. They
1
See, however, Frank (1973), who is highly skeptical about the abilities of judges and juries to
rationallydecide questions of fact.
Is There Only One Correct Legal Answer? 479
Ratio Juris, Vol. 29, No. 4 V
C2016 The Author. Ratio Juris V
C2016 John Wiley & Sons Ltd.

To continue reading

Request your trial

VLEX uses login cookies to provide you with a better browsing experience. If you click on 'Accept' or continue browsing this site we consider that you accept our cookie policy. ACCEPT