Getting Real or Staying Positive: Legal Realism(s), Legal Positivism and the Prospects of Naturalism in Jurisprudence

Published date01 December 2016
AuthorJakob v. H. Holtermann
DOIhttp://doi.org/10.1111/raju.12071
Date01 December 2016
Getting Real or Staying Positive:
Legal Realism(s), Legal Positivism
and the Prospects of Naturalism
in Jurisprudence*
JAKOB V. H. HOLTERMANN
Abstract. The relationship between Legal Realism and Legal Positivism has been a
recurrent source of debate. The question has been further complicated by the
related difficulty of assessing the internal relationship between the two main
original strands of Legal Realism: American and Scandinavian. This paper suggests
considering American and Scandinavian Realism as instantiations of forward-looking
and backward-looking rule skepticism respectively. This distinction brings into sharp
relief not only the fundamentally different relationship between each of these two
Realist schools and Legal Positivism but also their equally different potentials as
starting points for naturalizing jurisprudence.
1. Introduction
The relationship between Legal Realism and Legal Positivism has been a constant
source of debate since the emergence of Realist theories in the first half of the
twentieth century. The discussion has been further complicated by the related
difficulty of assessing the internal relationship between the two main original
strands of Legal Realism: American and Scandinavian.
More is at stake in this debate than taxonomic neatness. At stake are wide-
reaching methodological questions as to what kind of a science the study of law
should be according to Legal Realism. These questions are often formulated in a
modern context as questions about the potential for naturalism in legal science, i.e.
* An earlier version of this paper was presented at the conference “New Frontiers of Legal
Realism: American, Scandinavian, European, Global” at the Carlsberg Academy in Copen-
hagen, 29–30 May 2012. I am grateful to participants in the conference for rewarding
discussion. In particular, I recall valuable comments from Victoria Nourse, Gregory Shaffer,
Brian Leiter, Mikael Rask Madsen, Henrik Palmer Olsen, Torben Spaak, and Frederick
Schauer. I am also grateful to Enrico Pattaro for highly valuable comments. This research is
funded by the Danish National Research Foundation Grant no. DNRF105 and conducted
under the auspices of the Danish National Research Foundation’s Centre of Excellence for
International Courts (iCourts).
Ratio Juris. Vol. •• No. •• •• 2015 (••–••)
© 2015 The Author. Ratio Juris © 2015 John Wiley& Sons Ltd, 9600 Garsington Road, Oxford OX4 2DQ, UK and 350 Main
Street, Malden 02148, USA.
THE NOTEBOOK CORNER
* An earlier version of this paper was presented at the conference “New Frontiers of Legal
Realism: American, Scandinavian, European, Global” at the Carlsberg Academy in Copenha-
gen, 29–30 May 2012. I am grateful to participants at the conference for rewarding
discussion. In particular, I recall valuable comments from Victoria Nourse, Gregory Shaffer,
Brian Leiter, Mikael Rask Madsen, Henrik Palmer Olsen, Torben Spaak, and Frederick
Schauer. I am also grateful to Enrico Pattaro for highly valuable comments. This research is
funded by the Danish National Research Foundation Grant no. DNRF105 and conducted
under the auspices of the Danish National Research Foundation’s Centre of Excellence for
International Courts (iCourts).
V
C2015 The Author. Ratio Juris V
C2015 John Wiley & Sons Ltd, 9600 Garsington Road, Oxford OX4 2DQ, UK and 350 Main
Street, Malden 02148, USA.
Ratio Juris. Vol. 29 No. 4 December 2016 (535–555)
for associating the study of law with the ongoing empirical turn in epistemology
and philosophy of science which implies that these previously a priori disciplines
be transformed into empirical knowledge and science studies under the slogan:
“Out of the armchair and into the field!” (Dennett 1988).
Much confusion in the present debate seems to stem from a failure to correctly
identify the kind of rule-skepticism underlying Realism—or from the related failure
to correctly identify possible differences on this issue between the two kinds of
Realism. The canonical understanding of the rule-skepticism of Legal Realism has
become known in the literature as conceptual rule-skepticism. It was Hart who
originally ascribed this view to Legal Realism (see Hart 1959, 1994), and he is also
the one who has been credited with formulating a decisive argument against it.
According to Hart, conceptual rule-skepticism is the view that:
all talk of rules, and the corresponding words like ‘must’, ‘ought’, and ‘should’, is fraught
with a confusion which perhaps enhances their importance in men’s eyes but has no rational
basis. We merely think, so such critics claim, that there is something in the rule which binds
us to do certain things and guides or justifies us in doing them, but this is an illusion even
if it is a useful one. All that there is, over and above the clear ascertainable facts of group
behaviour and predictable reaction to deviation, are our own powerful “feelings” of com-
pulsion to behave in accordance with the rule and to act against those who do not. (Hart 1994,
11)
Specifically with regard to legal rules, conceptual rule-skepticism is the view “that
to assert the validity of a rule is to predict that it will be enforced by courts or some
other official action taken” (Hart 1994, 104).1
The problem with this kind of rule-skepticism which Hart pointed to is that it
leaves legal theory incapable of explaining how rules function in judicial decisions:
This cannot be its meaning in the mouth of a judge who is not engaged in predicting his own
or others’ behaviour or feelings. “This is a valid rule of law” said by a judge is an act of
recognition; in saying it he recognises the rule in question as one satisfying certain general
criteria for admission as a rule of the system and as a legal standard of behaviour. (Hart 1959,
237)2
This criticism launched by Hart has been extremely influential, and it arguably
bears a considerable part of the responsibility for the somewhat marginalized role
played by Legal Realism since then, at least in philosophical circles. In the present
context it may also be conceded, at least for the sake of argument, that Hart’s
famous argument is actually aimed at the kind of “conceptual rule-skepticism” he
described above. The only problem is that the argument is fundamentally mis-
guided qua criticism of both American and Scandinavian Legal Realism. It is
misguided mainly because Hart fails with this account to adequately capture the
1See also e.g. Hart 1994, 136–7. Ascribing this view to legal Realism seems at least
superficially well motivated in that it takes its cues from central quotes in the Realist
literature. See e.g. Holmes (1897, 461) and Karl N. Llewellyn (2008, 7) with regard to American
Legal Realism, and Ross (1953, 55 / 1958, 42) with regard to Scandinavian Legal Realism.
(Ross’s main work Om ret og retfærdighed was first published in Danish in 1953. The work
appeared in English as On Law and Justice in 1958. I use the forward slash (“/”) to indicate
references to two editions of the same work. Thus, Ross 1953, 55 / 1958, 42 refers to the same
place in the Danish edition and the English-language edition.
2See also Hart 1994, 105.
2Jakob v. H. Holtermann
© 2015 The Author. Ratio Juris © 2015 John Wiley & Sons Ltd. Ratio Juris, Vol. ••, No. ••
536 Jakob v. H. Holtermann
V
C2015 The Author. Ratio Juris V
C2015 John Wiley & Sons Ltd. Ratio Juris, Vol. 29, No. 4

To continue reading

Request your trial

VLEX uses login cookies to provide you with a better browsing experience. If you click on 'Accept' or continue browsing this site we consider that you accept our cookie policy. ACCEPT