“Constitution (Written or Unwritten)”: Legitimacy and Legality in the Thought of John Rawls

Published date01 December 2018
Date01 December 2018
DOIhttp://doi.org/10.1111/raju.12222
© 2018 The Author. Ratio Juris © 2018 John Wile y & Sons Ltd
Ratio Juris. Vol. 31 No. 4 December 2018 (379395)
“Constitution (Written or Unwritten)”:
Legitimacy and Legality in the Thought
of John Rawls
FRANK I. MICHELMAN
Abstract. John Rawls proposed, as what he ca lled “the liberal principle of legitimac y,” that
coercive exercises of pol itical power can be justified to fre e and equal dissenters when “in
accordance with a const itution (written or unwritten) the e ssentials of which all c itizens, as
reasonable and rationa l, can endorse.” Does “unwritten constitution” there refer to nor ms
of constitutional i mport, but that subsist only as custom, not as law? To norms that subsist
as common law but not as code law? To empirical regula rities of political practice, as op-
posed to normative rule s and standards? Which inter pretation is best?
1. Introduction: “Constit ution” in the “Liberal Pr inciple of Legitimacy”
Inevitably, in our world, a free and democratic society is a home to persons and
groups holding to a clashing plural ity of moral, philosophical, and religious orienta-
tions.1 But then how does such a societ y handle the always latently coercive, but
never practically dispensable, regulatory p ower of a democratic statethe “political
power,” as John Rawls named and described it, “of free and equal citizens as a col-
lective body,” which “they impose on thems elves and one another as free and
equal?” “In the light of what reasons and values,” Rawls wanted to know, could
democratic citizens hope to just ify to each other as free and eq ual their coercive
impositionspolitical majorities over dissentersby votes touching fundamenta l
matters over which they are morally, philosophically, and religiously divided?2
Rawls called that a problem of democratic political “legiti macy.”3
In Political Liberalism (hereinafter someti mes PL), Rawls responded to that prob-
lem with a proposition that does indeed ma ke its appeal to reasons and values, but
which quite striki ngly stipulates also for a specified i nstitutional form, that is, a
constitution. “Our exercise of political power is proper and hence justifi able,” Rawls
offered in PL,
1 See Rawls 1993, 36–7 (“fact of reasonable pluralism”); ibid., xviii (taking as a prem ise that “a
plurality of reasonable yet i ncompatible doctrines is t he normal result of the exerc ise of human
reason withi n [a] framework of [...] free institutions”).
2 Rawls 2001, 40–1; see Rawls 1993, 136–7, 216–7 (all posing the same question in es sentially
identical terms).
3 Rawls 2001, 40–1. Rawls also called thi s “the problem of political liberalism” (ibid., ix–xx).
Frank I. Michelman
380
Ratio Juris, Vol. 31, No. 4© 2018 The Author. Ratio Juris © 2018 John Wile y & Sons Ltd
only when it is exercised i n accordance with a constitution t he essentials of which all c itizens
may reasonably be expect ed to endorse in the light of principles a nd ideals acceptable to them
as reasonable and rationa l. This is the liberal pr inciple of legitimacy.4
Rawls named that, as you see, “the liberal principle of legitimacy.” I call it
hereinafter Rawls’s LPL. The LPL presents us with an obje ct-class, “constitution,”
of which some members do and some do not, in certai n essential respects, meet
a test of hypothetical reason able acceptability spelled out (more or less) by the
LPL. The LPL, then, lets justif ication ride on the back of a constitution that meets
the test.
I ask you now, before going on, to draw your mental picture of the “constitu-
tion” Rawls here has in view. What does it look like? Is it the kind of constitu-
tion Americans k now, a canonically scripted f ixture in a country ’s system of
positive prescriptive law? Did Rawls, then, by his statements of the LPL (“proper
and hence justifiable only when [...]”), render his stance adverse to that of those
Britons (say) who resist or deplore an introduction into their country’s political
practice of legal limitations on t he sovereignty of Parliament?5 The work in PL
contains a sign that he did not wi sh or mean to do so;6 but did he do so all the
sam e?
1.1. An Exegetical Question
PLs statement of the LPL is not the only one Rawls penned at about the same t ime.
In Justice as Fairness: A Restatem ent (hereinafter sometimes JF), the LPL appears as
follows:
Political power is legitimate on ly when it is exercised in accordance with a co nstitution (writ-
ten or unwritten) the es sentials of which all citiz ens, as reasonable and rational, can endorse
in the light of thei r common human reason. This i s the liberal principle of legitimac y. (Rawls
200 1, 41)
In the place of “constitution” in the PL version of the LPL, the JF rendition uses
“constitution (written or unwritten).” By a “written” constitution, Rawls would seem
to have meant the American model I strongly suspe ct you have just been picturing
in your own head. And what, then, of “unwritten?” Did Rawls thus mean, in JF, to
convey a significant modificat ion to the LPL of PL? Does “constitution (written or
unwritten)” in JF signify h is acceptance there of the possible sufficiency, to bear the
load of the justification of the force of democratic law, of something that is identi fi-
able as a country’s “constitution” but deviates from the standard written model? In
what way deviates?
If or insofar as the t wo worksPL and JFmight be in some such respect at
odds, presumably the more recent text should rule. PL appeared i n 1993. The man-
uscript for JFso that book’s editor adviseswas mai nly completed by 1989, but
4 Rawls 1993, 217. Compare Rawls 1993, 137: “Our exercise of politica l power is fully proper
only when it is exercised i n accordance with a constitution t he essentials of which all c itizens
as free and equa l can be expected to endorse in t he light of principles and ideals acceptable to
their common huma n reason. This is the li beral principle of legitimacy.”
5 See Delaney 2014, 548–55 (reviewing Br itish debates).
6 See Rawls 1993, 234–5, discuss ed below, six paragraphs into the section titled “T he Evidence
of Lecture IV.”

To continue reading

Request your trial

VLEX uses login cookies to provide you with a better browsing experience. If you click on 'Accept' or continue browsing this site we consider that you accept our cookie policy. ACCEPT