Can There Be an Artifact Theory of Law?

DOIhttp://doi.org/10.1111/raju.12134
Date01 September 2016
AuthorLuka Burazin
Published date01 September 2016
Can There Be an Artifact
Theory of Law?
LUKA BURAZIN*
Abstract. The idea that particular legal institutions are artifacts is not new. However,
the idea that the “law” or “legal system” is itself an artifact has seldom been directly
put forward, due perhaps to the ambiguities surrounding philosophical inquiries
into law. Nevertheless, such an idea has recently been invoked more often, though
not always developed in detail in terms of what the characterization of the “law” or
“legal system” as an artifact entails ontologically, and what consequences, if any,
this has for philosophical accounts of law. As a result, the primary aim of this paper
is to attempt an inquiry into what the claim that “law” by its nature or character is
an artifact entails, and what an artifact theory of law might look like.
1. Introduction
The idea that particular legal institutions are artifacts is not new. It seems intui-
tively correct to say that a particular legal institution, e.g., a mortgage or a leasing
contract, could not exist unless somebody intentionally created it. However, due
perhaps to the ambiguities surrounding philosophical inquiries into law, the idea
that “law” itself is an artifact has seldom been directly expressed, with some nota-
ble exceptions that have emerged in the recent debate. An example of the formula-
tion of such an idea is to be found in a recent paper by Leiter:
The concept of law is the concept of an artefact, that is, something that necessarily owes its
existence to human activities intended to create that artefact. Even John Finnis, our leading
natural law theorist, does not deny this point. I certainly do not understand Kelsen, Hart,
Raz, Dickson or Shapiro to deny this claim. Those who might want to deny that law is an
artefact concept are not my concern here; the extravagance of their metaphysical commit-
ments would, I suspect, be a subject for psychological, not philosophical investigation. (Leiter
2011, 666; footnotes omitted)
Despite the fact that the idea of “law” as an artifact has recently been invoked in
the legal-philosophical literature (Ehrenberg 2009, 91–113; Gardner 2004, 168–81;
Leiter 2011, 663–77; Schauer 2012, 457–67), this idea was not always developed in
* I am grateful to LynneRudder Baker and Risto Hilpinen as well as to two anonymousreferees
for valuablecomments on an earlier draft of this paper.The paper was written within the frame-
work of the ZagrebFaculty of Law research project “NewCroatian Legal System.”
V
C2016 The Author. Ratio Juris V
C2016 John Wiley & Sons Ltd, 9600 Garsington Road, Oxford OX4 2DQ, UK and 350 Main
Street, Malden 02148, USA.
Ratio Juris. Vol. 29 No. 3 September 2016 (385–401)
detail with regard to the questions of what the claim of the “law” or “legal system”
as an artifact entails ontologically and what consequences, if any, this claim has for
philosophical accounts of law.
As a brief preliminary remark I should point out that the artifact theory I
develop in this paper takes as its object “law” in the sense of the legal system. Thus
I circumvent the usual vagueness and confusion relating to the subject matter of
various philosophical inquires into “law,” since they sometimes aim at “law” qua
idea, sometimes qua social institution, sometimes qua social practice, and some-
times qua legal norms. The working definition of legal systems adopted for the
purposes of this paper conceptualizes legal systems as systems of legal norms (in
the sense of the meanings of norms), and as systems that are by and large
efficacious.
Broadly speaking, there are natural kinds and human (or social) kinds. Artifact
kinds, no doubt, belong to the latter group. Natural kinds are groups of objects
(things, entities) naturally brought into existence, the grouping (sorting, ordering)
of which does not depend on humans, but on their natural common properties
(e.g., the atomic structure, DNA types). It may thus be assumed that natural objects
have essences and that it is possible to identify a set of necessary and sufficient
conditions for natural-kind membership. In contrast, artifact kinds are groups of
objects (artifacts) intentionally produced for some purpose, and the grouping of
these objects is not fixed by nature, but depends on human understanding and
agency. It may thus be said that artifacts do not have “real,” ontologically objective
essences,
1
but that their “nature” is constituted by the concepts and intentions of
artifact authors (creators, makers) and that these, in turn, determine what features
are relevant for an artifact to be a member of a certain artifact kind.
2
If one is to accept the claim that the “legal system” is an artifact kind, one has to
answer several important ontological, semantic, epistemological, psychological,
and methodological questions: concerning the nature of the legal system viewed as
an artifact kind, those of determining the reference of legal systems as artifact kinds
and our epistemic relationship to them, concerning the ways of classifying them in
kinds, and concerning the appropriate methodology for theorizing about them.
These questions will be discussed within the scope of a broader project I pursue,
which I refer to as the “artifact theory of law.”
Since this is a preliminary investigation, this paper aims at attempting an inquiry
into what the claim that “law” by its nature or character is an artifact would entail
and what, in the end, an artifact theory of law might look like. Before embarking
on such an inquiry, I will, however, first try to indicate at least some potential pay-
offs of the artifactual understanding of law (Section 2). In order to be able to
answer certain ontological questions concerning legal systems as artifact kinds, I
will outline in the following a general theory of artifacts (Section 3). I will do this
by exploring several theories of artifacts developed in general philosophy, drawing
1
The term real (ontologically objective essence) is understood as “real according to the criteria
for existencesuitable for members of natural kinds.”
2
For such a view, which nevertheless defends the reality of artifacts (and so their place in the
ontological inventory), see, e.g., Thomasson 2007. For the opposite view, according to which at
least some artifacts (those which are “copied kinds”) are “real” because they have mind-
independentnatures just like natural kinds,see, e.g., Elder 2007.
386 Luka Burazin
V
C2016 The Author. Ratio Juris V
C2016 John Wiley & Sons Ltd. Ratio Juris, Vol. 29, No. 3

To continue reading

Request your trial

VLEX uses login cookies to provide you with a better browsing experience. If you click on 'Accept' or continue browsing this site we consider that you accept our cookie policy. ACCEPT