Against Parochialism in Contract Theory: A Response to Brian Bix

Date01 June 2019
AuthorFelipe Jiménez
Published date01 June 2019
DOIhttp://doi.org/10.1111/raju.12237
© 2019 The Author. Ratio Juris © 2019 John Wi ley & Sons Ltd.
Ratio Juris. Vol. 32 No. 2 June 2019 (233250)
Against Parochialism in Contract
Theory: A Response to Brian Bix
FELIPE JIMÉNEZ
1. Introduction
There is plenty to agree with in Brian Bix’s recent article problematizing u niversal
and general theories of contract law (Bix 2017).1 Bix is certainly right to note that
most contract theorists— and private law theorists, for that matter—are typically
silent about the types of clai ms they make and the scope and ambitions of t heir the-
ories.2 He is also right about the m ismatch between the usually (implicit) universal
scope of theories and their parochial focu s on one or a small number of related
national jurisdictions.3 Fi nally, I entirely agree with Professor Bix’s worries about the
Dworkinian identification between the logical space occupied by adjudication and
legal theory (Bix 2017, 394),4 as well as with his concern s about the theoretical
inflation that ch aracterizes contemporary contract theory (Bix 2017, 396).
Despite these agreements, in th is partial response I wish to suggest that Bix’s
concerns about universal theories of cont ract law should not lead us towards a pref-
erence for localized, parochial theories of contract law.5 What I wish to suggest,
more precisely, is that Bix’s concerns should not lead to parochialism—i.e., the idea
that local or parochia l theories of contract law are always preferable to universal
theories. On the contrar y, as this paper arg ues, there are good reasons to think t hat
a universal approach to contract theory m ight be warranted. For this pur pose,
Section 2 explain s what I take to be the right subject matter to be t heorized by uni-
versal contract theory, and in what sense th is approach is—and is not—“universal,”
as well as the kind of argument that should be put forward to defend such an
approach. Sections 3 to 6 contain t he substance of the argu ment in favor of this
transnational a nd universal approach towards contract theory. Finally, Section 7
1 Which refi nes and extends prior arguments m ade in Bix 2007 and 2013, 147–62.
2 A notable exception is Smith 200 4.
3 Others have already notice d the worrying par ochiali sm of most contemporary Anglo -
American contract t heory. See Murphy 2014, 152.
4 For Dworkin, legal theor y is the “silent prologue” to adjudicative decisions. S ee Dworkin
1986, 90 .
5 Thus, I leave aside in this res ponse Bix’s arguments against genera l theories of contract law.
Notes • Discussions • Book Reviews
Felipe Jiménez
234
Ratio Juris, Vol. 32, No. 2© 2019 The Author. Ratio Juris © 2019 John Wi ley & Sons Ltd.
concludes and suggests that, at least in one respect, a un iversal approach can even be
preferable over more local approaches.
2. “Universal” Contrac t Theory
Universal contract theory should theor ize institutional practices of contract law. By an
institutional practice, I understand “a sort of technical term meaning any form of
activity specified by a system of r ules which defines offices, roles, moves, penalties,
defenses, and so on, and which gives the activity its structure” (Rawls 1955, 3 n. 1).
The focus should thus be on the for ms of activities specified by the systems of con-
tract law and the institutional definitions of rights, duties, and remedies that they
generate. An institutional practice, moreover, in the way I am using the term, is a
system of rules, i.e., authoritative legal norms.6 Inst itutional practices of contract law,
then, are systems of legal norms wh ich regulate exchange by defi ning, inter alia,
what constitutes an enforceable contract, as well as how contracts should be inter-
preted, performed, and enforced.7
Of course, the institution of contract law can also do other thi ngs. In addition it
might, as it in fact does in certain jurisdictions, enforce unilateral u ndertakings
which do not amount to “exchange.”8 It might al so give rise to other legal in stitu-
tions—thi nk, for instance, about partnership agreements, or contracts of marriage.
From jurisdiction to juri sdiction, contract law might also encompass larger or
smaller areas of human i nteraction. But I am not too concerned, in this paper, with
demarcating or policing contract law’s boundaries. My concern, rather, is whether
contract law, understood as a system of legal norms that regulates the exchange of
goods and services, can be usefully and legitimately theorized from a “universal”
perspective.
As such a system, contract law provides individuals with r ights-creating powers
(Hart 1994, 41). It is a set of power-conferring rules (ibid., 96; Raz 1999, 104–6) that
enables individuals to create and alter private rights and duties (Barnett 2010, xix).
When a contract is validly executed (and it is a crucial role of contract law that it
determines the conditions of such validity), correlative primary rights and duties
arise. At the same time, contract law also imposes secondary duties in cases of
breach of those primar y duties. Its rules are thus also duty-imposing.9
From this perspective, what universal contract theory should theorize are the
“salient features of a modern municipal legal system” (Hart 1994, 100, 240) of con-
tract law. Thus, the subject of analysis should not be a partic ular jurisdiction but the
practice of contract law, the characterization of which is given by the core featu res
6 Because of this br oad use of the term rules as legal norms, it should be u nderstood that the
term as I use it does not exclude, as some d iscussions i n jurisprudence could sug gest, stan-
dards or formally en acted legal principles.
7 For this charact erization, I reviewed se veral comparative contract law and Amer ican con-
tract law textbooks, al l of which showed a remarkable degre e of consistency in t he topics
covered. See, just as examples, Bar nett 2010; Beale, Bishop, and Fur mston 2007; Beatson 2002;
Bix 2013; Farnsworth et al. 2008; Graziano 20 09; Levasseur 2008; and Zweigert and Kötz 1998,
323–536.
8 See, e.g., Restatement (Second) of Contracts par. 90 (1979).
9 Because of this, K lass (2008) is right when he labels t he rules of contract law as co mpound
rules.

To continue reading

Request your trial

VLEX uses login cookies to provide you with a better browsing experience. If you click on 'Accept' or continue browsing this site we consider that you accept our cookie policy. ACCEPT