After Exception: Carl Schmitt's Legal Institutionalism and the Repudiation of Exceptionalism

Published date01 September 2016
AuthorMariano Croce,Andrea Salvatore
Date01 September 2016
DOIhttp://doi.org/10.1111/raju.12119
After Exception: Carl Schmitt’s Legal
Institutionalism and the Repudiation
of Exceptionalism
MARIANO CROCE and ANDREA SALVATORE
In the most classical and abstract sense, the exception is the “miraculous” moment
of the sovereign decision where the borders between the inside and the outside are
fixed through the identification of the enemy. This is a Schmittian legacy that a
growing number of theoretical paradigms today look at in order to either build on
it or to debunk it. For some interpreters, exceptionalism is a perceptive analysis of
the way political power takes hold of society; for others, it is a misleading and mys-
tifying hypothesis that may even end up justifying the increasing overuse of emer-
gency powers all over the world.
Whether or not exceptionalism has something sensible to say about today’s poli-
tics, in this article we will argue that Carl Schmitt himself, the recognized father of
this paradigm, came to the conclusion that it is not ultimately tenable. Between the
end of the 1920s and the beginning of the 1930s, Schmitt extensively revised his
view of law and politics in light of legal institutionalism, a theory that considered
law in general to be connected to the phenomenon of social organization and the
legal order to be rooted in the laborious and enduring activity of social actors.
The present article pursues three chief aims. First, we will provide grounds for
holding that Schmitt’s theory as a whole cannot be read through the lens of excep-
tionalism and decisionism. Secondly, we will explain the reasons why he decided
to reconsider his approach. Thirdly, and more importantly, not only will our analy-
sis aim to provide a better understanding of Schmitt’s thinking, but it will also, and
perhaps primarily, aim to shed some light on the limits of exceptionalism by trac-
ing the tormented path followed by its inventor.
In order to achieve these aims, we will first illustrate why the exceptionalist read-
ing of Schmitt does not hold (Section 1). Then we will discuss the impact of institu-
tionalism on Schmitt’s overall theory (Section 2). We will go on to explore Schmitt’s
particular version of institutionalism, as it reveals the chasm between a paradigm
based on the exception and one that recognizes the foundational and vital role
of social practices (Section 3). Finally, we will make the claim that Schmitt did
away with exceptionalism precisely because of its abstract and paradoxical nature
(Section 4).
V
C2016 John Wiley & Sons Ltd, 9600 Garsington Road, Oxford OX4 2DQ, UK and 350 Main Street, Malden 02148, USA.
Ratio Juris. Vol. 29 No. 3 September 2016 (410–426)
1. Schmitt and Decisionism: A Lasting (and Equivocal) Relationship
The recent, remarkable revival in academic interest in Schmitt’s thought appears
very different from the first wave, which occurred in the 1980s, at least in a crucial
respect: Scholars as well as political observers have focused their attention on differ-
ent writings and with different aims. Whereas the first reappraisal was mainly con-
fined to Schmitt’s critique of the liberal conception of politics and, more specifically,
of parliamentary democracy, this second and ongoing renaissance mainly deals with
Schmitt’s international thought and the underlying rejection of any form of imperial
order, on the one extreme, and a pervasive state of anarchy, on the other.
1
Corre-
spondingly, whereas the first revival was led by the intent to unmask what many
considered as the essential flaws and the unkept promises of the liberal-democratic
model that was definitely defeating the Communist alternative, the second tackles
the problem of the post-9/11 world order and the quest for a new nomos.
However, despite their diversity, these two revivals share a key feature: In both
cases, Schmitt is read and interpreted through the lens of the concepts of decision
and exception. Whether it is meant to justify (or at least to account for) an irrecon-
cilable opposition between two (or more) conflicting social groups (mainly for the
first revival) or to comment on the ongoing rise of states of emergency (mainly for
the second), in either case the decisionism-exceptionalism dyad represents the her-
meneutical background against which scholars provide their interpretation of
Schmitt’s thought as a whole. To put it otherwise, regardless of any other critical
consideration and theoretical development, Schmitt’s legal and political theory is
substantially reduced to what is largely recognized as its foundational and thus
ever-present decisionist core. Accordingly, the immediate identification of
Schmitt’s theory with decisionism is widely regarded as a platitude, if not a truism.
This reading has induced most interpreters to look at each of Schmitt’s positions
through the lens of his decisionist approach and thus to regard his own later rejec-
tion of decisionism as nothing but a contingent and self-interested move. As an
epitome of this widespread tendency, a prominent scholar stated that “Schmitt’s
own theory is justly described as ‘decisionism.’ He scorned bargaining and the rule
of law, while apotheosizing ‘hard’ political decisions—the choice of an enemy, for
example, or the decision to suspend the constitution and rule by means of the
Reichswehr” (Holmes 1996, 47). On the same wavelength, another commentator
argued that “Schmitt’s voluminous pre-war (WWII) writings on politics and juris-
prudence, on which his current fame rests, can all be read as applications of the
principles of political enmity and sovereign decisionism formulated in The Concept
of the Political” (Lilla 2001, 59).
2
We believe these readings to be mistaken precisely because, in keeping with a
longstanding and still widespread tradition, they put decisionism at the heart of
Schmitt’s overall theory of law and politics. We claim that decisionism, far from
1
Two telling examples of books which aim to introduce Schmitt’s international thought to
Global Studiesand International Relationsare Hooker 2010 and Odysseosand Petito 2009.
2
This interpretive framework was originally adopted in Krockow 1958 and Schwab 1970, that
is, the two pioneering presentations of Schmitt’s thought. It is no coincidence that both of these
books respectively mention the terms decision and exception in their title. For a more recent
endorsementof this interpretation, see Agamben2005.
After Exception: Carl Schmitt's Legal Institutionalism 411
Ratio Juris, Vol. 29, No. 3 V
C2016 John Wiley & Sons Ltd.

To continue reading

Request your trial

VLEX uses login cookies to provide you with a better browsing experience. If you click on 'Accept' or continue browsing this site we consider that you accept our cookie policy. ACCEPT