The Common Core between Human Rights Law and International Criminal Law: A Structural Account

DOIhttp://doi.org/10.1111/raju.12254
Date01 September 2019
Published date01 September 2019
2019 The Author. Ratio Juris © 2019 John Wi ley & Sons Ltd.
Ratio Juris. Vol. 32 No. 3 September 2019 (278–300)
The Common Core between Human
Rights Law and International Criminal
Law: A Structural Account
ALAIN ZYSSET*
Abstract. Legal schola rs and theorists have recently drawn a more sust ained attention to the
link betwe en international human r ights law (hereafter IHRL) and intern ational crimina l law
(hereafter ICL). This concer ns both positive and more normative accou nts of the link. Whethe r
positive or normative, the predomin ant approach to constructing the l ink is substantive. This
overlap is normatively justified i n similar ter ms by reference to a subset of moral hu man rights.
In this paper, I offer an alter native to the substantive approach. After identif ying two flaws
in the substant ive approach (the problem of threshold and the pr oblem of ethical neutrality), I
defend what I call a struct ural account by focusing on duty-holders. I sta rt by reconstructing
two structu ral characteri stics common to IHRL a nd ICL qua international le gal regimes:
who has the authorit y to address violations of I HRL and ICL, and who can be liable for those
violations. I then in fer that public authority (functio nally construe d) constitutes the com mon
structura l core of IHRL and ICL. I rely on the extraterritorial applic ation of IHRL and on the
collective dimen sion of ICL violations to furt her support the arg ument. I final ly offer an
argument explai ning the normative point of those struc tural features. I hold that IHRL and
ICL (their adjudicative and liabilit y regimes) are both necessary ( but clearly not sufficient) to
render this exerci se of public authority legitimate to its subje cts.
1. Introduction
Legal scholars have recently drawn a more susta ined attention to the link between
international huma n rights law (hereafter, IHRL) and international c rimina l law
(hereafter, ICL). One predominant approach to this lin k is to identify the overlap that
may exist be tween international crimes a nd human rights violations—in partic ular,
when and why certain human r ights violations may constitute international cri mes.
This is the cas e, for instance, with crimes aga inst humanity; A ndrew Clapham
(2016, 17) argue s that “systematic violations of human r ights are associated with the
* I am ver y grateful to the pa rticipants in t he workshop Answering for Internation al Crimes:
Perspectives from Moral, Political and Legal T heory (July 2017) at PluriCourts, University of Oslo,
and to an anonymous rev iewer of Ratio Juris for very constr uctive and insightful com ments. I
am particul arly indebted to Alejandro Chehtm an, Andreas Follesdal, and Malcol m Thorburn
for continuously discu ssing of the topic in recent years.
279
Ratio Juris, Vol. 32, No. 3 2019 The Author. Ratio Juris © 2019 John Wi ley & Sons Ltd.
The Common Core
prospect of prosecuting t he perpetrators for crimes aga inst humanit y.” In the case
of genocide, Robert Cryer (2010, 499) holds that “these types of acts can amou nt to a
violation of civil and political rig hts.
A similar tre nd can be found in the normative theory of IHRL and ICL. I n this lit-
erature, Massimo Renzo, for insta nce, identifies “dignity” as the com mon core pro-
tected by both IHRL and ICL (with specif ic reference to crimes agai nst humanity):
“crimes against humanity a re those which deny their vic tims the statu s of human
being, i.e., those crimes that violate basic huma n rights of their victims” (Renzo 2012,
453). Numerous contributions to the normative theory of ICL more implicitly rely
on a notion of IHRL when they explain, for in stance, in what sense cri mes against
humanity concern hum anity at large. David Luban (2004, 44), for instance, contends
that the “claim that all human kind has an i nterest in repressing cr imes against
human ity presupposes at the very least a universal human right not to be subj ected
to these crimes.” This u nifying approach is substantive in postu lating a substantive
and universal status or value —one that justifies the extraterritorial reg imes associ-
ated with IHRL and ICL.
In this paper, I offer an alternative to the substa ntive approach. I defend what I
call a “structural” account of the li nk between IHRL and ICL. Instead of focusi ng on
the limited overlap between the t wo types of violations, I start by reconstr ucting two
structural c haracteristics that are intrigu ingly common to the international regi mes
of IHRL and ICL: who has the authority to adjudicate violations of IHRL and ICL,
and who c an be liable for these violations. In ot her words, I suggest concentrating
on duty- holders u nder IHRL and ICL to build their com mon core. The conventional
notion used to address those quest ions is jurisdiction (to legislate, to adjudicate, and
to enforce). But jurisdiction in this context i s simply another word to signify th at
some legal official is con ferred authority over the creation, adjudication, and/or the
enforcement of international lega l norms, as I shall explain.
More importantly, opting for the structu ral approach supposes that the substan-
tive approach is deficient. First, the substantive approach faces a thresh old problem.
Once one postulates that IHR L and ICL protect a substantive moral status or value
(such as “dignity”), it quickly appears that a vast range of rights and crim inal prohibi-
tions may also protect th at status without forming part of the conventional corpus of
IHRL and ICL. The criterion for dist inguishing ICL and IHRL f rom their domestic an-
alogues (constitutional law and cri minal law, respectively) thereby collapses. Second,
adopting the substantive approach risks conveyi ng a comprehensive moral view of
what the violations of norms indeed attac k—call it the problem of ethical neutrality.
This problem is even more acute in the context of inter national law, since imposing a
comprehensive moral view would ultimately conflict w ith the state’s basic moral right
to self-determination (and its legal counter part in Article 1(2) of the UN Charter). This
in no way diminishe s the idea that ICL violations “shock the conscience of humanity”
(Preamble to the Rome Statute of the Internationa l Crimina l Court). It rather places
a normative constraint on the spec ification of what exactly those violations attack.
Once the limits of the sub stantive approach are established, it remains to be seen
what the structural approach ca n deliver. This approach asks two questions: Who
is entitled to adjudicate IHRL and ICL violations? And who is liable for those v io-
lations? I suggest that these criteria should i nform the normative elucidation of the
common core between IHRL and ICL. T he fact that they are struct ural—they form
part of the basic legal architec ture of these reg imes—furt her invites us to explore

To continue reading

Request your trial

VLEX uses login cookies to provide you with a better browsing experience. If you click on 'Accept' or continue browsing this site we consider that you accept our cookie policy. ACCEPT