Perfect regular equilibrium

Published date01 December 2020
DOIhttp://doi.org/10.1111/ijet.12199
Date01 December 2020
doi: 10.1111/ijet.12199
Perfect regular equilibrium
Hanjoon Michael Jung
We extend the solution concept of perfect Bayesian equilibrium to general games that allow a
continuum of types and strategies. In finite games, a perfect Bayesian equilibrium is weakly con-
sistent and a subgame perfect Nash equilibrium. In general games, however,it might not satisfy
these criteria. To solve this problem, we revise the definition of perfect Bayesian equilibrium
by replacing Bayes’ rule with regular conditional probability. The revised solution concept is
referred to as perfect regular equilibrium. Wepresent the conditions that ensure the existence of
this equilibrium. Then we show that every perfect regular equilibrium is always weakly consistent
and a subgame perfect Nashequilibr ium, and is equivalentto a simple version of perfect Bayesian
equilibrium in a finite game.
Key wor ds Bayes’rule, general game, perfect Bayesian equilibrium, perfect regular equilibrium,
regular conditional probability, solution concept
JEL classification C72
Accepted 13 January 2018
1 Introduction
We propose a revised version of perfect Bayesian equilibrium in general multi-period games with
observed actions, which allow a continuum of types and strategies. Fudenberg and Tirole (1991)
formulated the perfect Bayesian equilibrium in the setting of finite multi-period games with observed
actions, which allow only a finite number of types and strategies. In the finite games, every perfect
Bayesian equilibrium satisfies weak consistencyand the subgame perfect Nash equilibrium condition.
However, it might not satisfy these criteria in general games. To solve this problem, we revise its
definition by replacing Bayes’ rule with regular conditional probability. We refer to this revised
version as perfect regular equilibrium. Weshow that it satisfies these criteria in general multi-period
games with observed actions.
In game theory, most of the solution concepts were developed as refinements of the Nash equi-
librium introduced by Nash (1951). A Nash equilibrium consists of a set of strategies for each player
such that each strategy is the best response to the other strategies. This Nash equilibrium became
known as a compelling condition for rational strategies, and thus it became a necessary condition for
rational solution concepts. However, the Nash equilibrium was defined in strategic form games in
which in which all players must choose their strategies once and simultaneously.Hence, this solution
concept may not properlypredict players’ behavior in multi-period games where players choose their
actions in each period after observing actions taken before. In the multi-period games, players can
Ma Yinchu School of Economics,Tianjin University, Tianjin, China. Email: junghanjoon73@hanmail.net
I am very grateful to the anonymous referee for his or her valuable comments that have improvedthis dr aft. I gratefully
acknowledge research support from the NationalScience Council of the Republic of China (NSC 99-2410-H-001-114).
International Journal of Economic Theory (2018) 1–19 © IAET 1
International Journal of Economic Theory 16 (2020) 380–398 © IAET
380
International Journal of Economic Theory
Perfect regular equilibrium Hanjoon Michael Jung
have different incentives in different periods. Since the Nash equilibrium requires all the players to
choose their strategies once and simultaneously, it might not reflect those various incentives in the
multi-period games. As a result, a Nash equilibrium may include incredible threats.
The subgame perfect Nash equilibrium by Selten (1975) improved the Nash equilibrium. The
basic idea behind this solution concept was to break a whole game into subgames and to find Nash
equilibria in every subgame. When we analyze each of the subgames separately,we are able to consider
players’ incentives within those subgames separately. Thus, the subgame perfect Nash equilibrium
can reflect different incentives in different subgames, and so it mayexclude some incredible threats.1
In games with incomplete information, however,subgames are too large to catch each of the players’
incentivesseparately. So, the subgame perfect Nash equilibrium might fail to reflect players’incentives
in different periods, which means that it may yet include incredible threats.
The perfect Bayesian equilibrium and the sequential equilibrium introduced by Kreps and Wil-
son (1982) improved the subgame perfect Nash equilibrium. These solution concepts breaka w hole
game into information sets and search strategies that satisfy sequential rationality for each of the
information sets. Sequential rationality is a condition for the strategies of rational players, and re-
quires that each strategy be the best response to the other strategies for each of the information
sets. This sequential rationality, therefore, inherits the spirit of the Nash equilibrium condition. In-
formation sets are small enough to represent each of the incentives separately. Consequently, these
solution concepts can reflect different incentives in different periods, and thus they can exclude
incredible threats in finite games. In general games that allow a continuum of types and strate-
gies, however, these solution concepts may cause more serious problems than including incredible
threats.
Information sets can be viewed as the smallest units of analysis. In games, players cannot distin-
guish decision points in a common information set. So, whatever action they choose, the same action
must be applied to all decision points in a common information set. That is, players can choose only
one action for each of their information sets. Hence, information sets would be the smallest units
that we can analyze in order to find players’ rational strategies.
These smallest units of analysis, however,might be too small for us to find rational strategies, and
sometimes we might need more information to find rational strategies for each of the information
sets. Sufficient information for finding rational strategies is constituted by rational beliefs, which
are probability distributions over each of the information sets and are also consistent with the given
strategies. For this reason, both of the solution concepts, perfect Bayesianequilibr ium and sequential
equilibrium, require specification of rational beliefs.
These solution concepts employ Bayes’ rule when they define the conditions for rational beliefs.
In general games, however,Bayes’ rule has limited application in practice, and this limited application
could result in their inability to satisfy weak consistency and the subgame perfect Nash equilibrium
condition.
Weak consistency is a criterion of rational beliefs, and it places restrictions only on the beliefs
on the equilibrium path. Weak consistency is viewed as a necessary condition for rational beliefs.
However, it is weak in that it does not locate any restriction on the beliefs off the equilibrium
path. The subgame perfect Nash equilibrium condition, on the other hand, is a criterion of the
rational strategies. It places restrictions on all actions on the equilibrium path, and furthermore it
sets restrictions on some of the actions off the equilibrium path. In this way, it can indirectly inspect
1Tofind a subgame perfect Nash equilibrium in practice, it is convenient to analyze subgames from back to front. This is
because, by analyzing backward, we can naturally consider players’future incentives in any period. In this sense, we may
view the subgame perfect Nash equilibrium as a combination of the Nash equilibrium and backward induction.
2International Journal of Economic Theory (2018) 1–19 © IAET
International Journal of Economic Theory 16 (2020) 380–398 © IAET 381

To continue reading

Request your trial

VLEX uses login cookies to provide you with a better browsing experience. If you click on 'Accept' or continue browsing this site we consider that you accept our cookie policy. ACCEPT