Legal Interpretation, Conceptual Ethics, and Alternative Legal Concepts
Published date | 01 December 2023 |
Author | David Plunkett |
Date | 01 December 2023 |
DOI | http://doi.org/10.1111/raju.12395 |
© 2023 University of Bologna and John Wiley & Sons Ltd.
Ratio Juris. Vol. 36 No. 4 December (286–313)
Legal Interpretation, Conceptual Ethics,
and Alternative Legal Concepts
DAVID PLUNKETT*
Abstract. When legal theorists ask questions about legal interpretation—such as what it funda-
mentally is, what it aims at, or how it should work—they often do so in ways closely tethered
to existing legal practice. For example: they try to understand how an activity legal actors (pur-
portedly) already engage in should be done better, such as how judges can better learn about
the content of the law. In this paper, I discuss a certain kind of “conceptual ethics” approach
to thinking about legal interpretation, which is less tethered to existing legal practice (or the
existing meaning of core pieces of legal terminology). The approach I explore asks questions
about legal interpretation in a way that is tethered to what legal (or “legal-ish”) concepts people
should deploy, as part of arguments on behalf of engaging in legal (or “legal-ish”) practices
different from our current ones. In exploring this approach, I aim to help us better understand
the landscape of philosophical issues about legal interpretation, including parts of it that I think
have been underexplored.
1. Introduction
A common claim about legal practice—endorsed by legal practitioners and theorists
alike—is that “legal interpretation” is an important activity that judges and other legal
actors engage in. There is a range of different questions that philosophers ask about
what legal interpretation is, or about what it should be. One important question is what
the success-conditions of legal interpretation as such are; or, put another way, what the
constitutive aim of legal interpretation is. Another question is how judges (or other legal
actors) should engage in legal interpretation: for example, whether they should use a
“textualist” interpretative method, which (put roughly) hews closely to the “original”
meaning of legal texts, or a “purposivist” one, which (put roughly) looks to uncover the
“purpose” behind legislation. These two questions are tied closely together. For if the
constitutive aim of legal interpretation is to X, this provides a standard with which to
evaluate proposals for how judges (or other legal actors) should engage in legal inter-
pretation: namely, we can ask how well those proposals would allow them to X.
* Thanks to Hrafn Asgeirsson, Mitch Berman, Benjamin Eidelson, Natalie Dokken, Max
Etchemendy, Mark Greenberg, Sean Kim, Zachary Lang, Tristram McPherson, Corrado Roversi,
Adrian Russian, Scott Shapiro, Tim Sundell, Zoe Thierfelder, Elmar Unnsteinsson, Fangzhou
Yu, and an anonymous referee for helpful discussion and feedback on this paper, or on ideas
connected to it. Earlier versions of this paper were presented at the University of Bologna, the
University of Iceland, and Dartmouth College. Thanks to everyone who participated in those
discussions.
287
Ratio Juris, Vol. 36, No. 4© 2023 University of Bologna and John Wiley & Sons Ltd.
Legal Interpretation, Conceptual Ethics, and Alternative Legal Concepts
When legal philosophers ask these (and other related) questions about legal inter-
pretation, they often do so in a way that is closely tethered to actual legal practice. In
short, they standardly want to better understand an activity (one aptly discussed as
“legal interpretation”) that legal actors already actually engage in, and how they
should do that activity, in order to do it better. In this paper, I want to put on the table
another set of questions about “legal interpretation” that are asked in a way that is
less tethered to actual legal practice. The questions are tied to a certain kind of “con-
ceptual ethics” approach to thinking about both “legal interpretation” and “law”. In
broad terms, the approach I explore asks questions about what legal (or “legal-ish”)
concepts people should deploy, as part of arguments on behalf of engaging in legal
(or “legal-ish”) practices different from our current ones. Somewhat more specifi-
cally, I focus on arguments that involve advocating for a change in what activity
should count as “legal interpretation” (at least in certain contexts), via making an
argument for shifting which concept the term ‘law’ (as used in stating a theory of
legal interpretation) is used to express.1 The idea of such an argument, in the versions
of it that I am interested in, is (roughly) to argue that certain people (e.g., certain
judges or legal theorists) should engage in this new activity (at least in certain con-
texts), rather than the activity we currently discuss as “legal interpretation”.
My aims in this paper with respect to this kind of approach to “legal interpreta-
tion” are relatively philosophically modest. I aim to get this sort of “conceptual eth-
ics” approach to issues about “legal interpretation” more clearly in view, and explore
how the issues it raises are distinct from other, related ones that have received more
sustained and more explicit critical attention. In discussing this approach, I aim to
help us better understand the landscape of philosophical issues about legal interpre-
tation, including parts of it that I think have been underexplored. Toward the end
of the paper, I also briefly discuss how issues raised by this approach might help us
see a certain kind of ideological role that statements about legal interpretation might
play, which we should be attentive to.
2. What Legal Interpretation Is
In order to situate the particular kind of conceptual ethics approach to “legal in-
terpretation” and “law” that I want to focus on in this paper—and the kinds of
distinctive issues it brings up—it will be helpful to say a bit more about the initial
two questions about legal interpretation that I introduced in the first paragraph
of the introduction. I will start by discussing them as asked in relatively standard
ways, which don’t have the same ties to the kinds of “reforming” or “revolution-
ary” views in conceptual ethics about ‘law’ that I eventually focus on. This will
help provide a useful contrast for better understanding the alternative kind of
approach I want to focus on.
Let’s start with the question about what the constitutive aim of legal interpreta-
tion is.
1 In this paper, I use single quotation marks (e.g., ‘shoe’) to mention linguistic items (as well as
to nest quotation marks within pairs of enclosing double quotation marks). I use double quota-
tion marks (e.g., “shoe”) for a variety of tasks including quoting others’ words, scare quotes,
and mixes of use and mention. I use small caps (e.g., ) to pick out concepts.
Get this document and AI-powered insights with a free trial of vLex and Vincent AI
Get Started for FreeUnlock full access with a free 7-day trial
Transform your legal research with vLex
-
Complete access to the largest collection of common law case law on one platform
-
Generate AI case summaries that instantly highlight key legal issues
-
Advanced search capabilities with precise filtering and sorting options
-
Comprehensive legal content with documents across 100+ jurisdictions
-
Trusted by 2 million professionals including top global firms
-
Access AI-Powered Research with Vincent AI: Natural language queries with verified citations

Unlock full access with a free 7-day trial
Transform your legal research with vLex
-
Complete access to the largest collection of common law case law on one platform
-
Generate AI case summaries that instantly highlight key legal issues
-
Advanced search capabilities with precise filtering and sorting options
-
Comprehensive legal content with documents across 100+ jurisdictions
-
Trusted by 2 million professionals including top global firms
-
Access AI-Powered Research with Vincent AI: Natural language queries with verified citations

Unlock full access with a free 7-day trial
Transform your legal research with vLex
-
Complete access to the largest collection of common law case law on one platform
-
Generate AI case summaries that instantly highlight key legal issues
-
Advanced search capabilities with precise filtering and sorting options
-
Comprehensive legal content with documents across 100+ jurisdictions
-
Trusted by 2 million professionals including top global firms
-
Access AI-Powered Research with Vincent AI: Natural language queries with verified citations

Unlock full access with a free 7-day trial
Transform your legal research with vLex
-
Complete access to the largest collection of common law case law on one platform
-
Generate AI case summaries that instantly highlight key legal issues
-
Advanced search capabilities with precise filtering and sorting options
-
Comprehensive legal content with documents across 100+ jurisdictions
-
Trusted by 2 million professionals including top global firms
-
Access AI-Powered Research with Vincent AI: Natural language queries with verified citations

Unlock full access with a free 7-day trial
Transform your legal research with vLex
-
Complete access to the largest collection of common law case law on one platform
-
Generate AI case summaries that instantly highlight key legal issues
-
Advanced search capabilities with precise filtering and sorting options
-
Comprehensive legal content with documents across 100+ jurisdictions
-
Trusted by 2 million professionals including top global firms
-
Access AI-Powered Research with Vincent AI: Natural language queries with verified citations
