Integrative Jurisprudence: Legal Scholarship and the Triadic Nature of Law

Date01 December 2020
DOIhttp://doi.org/10.1111/raju.12301
AuthorMatthias Klatt
Published date01 December 2020
© (2021) The Authors. Ratio Juris published by University of Bologna and John Wiley & Sons Ltd.
Ratio Juris, Vol. 33 No. 4 December 2020 (380–398)
Integrative Jurisprudence:
Legal Scholarship and the Triadic
Nature of Law
MATTHIAS KLATT
Abstract. What is the core of legal scholarship? How can we understand its relation to other
disciplines, such as moral and political philosophy, sociology, and economics? I explore these
questions by analysing the impact of the dual nature thesis. Criticising established theories of
legal scholarship, I defend the ideal of an integrative jurisprudence. Integrative jurisprudence
combines the two dimensions of law by employing analytical, empirical, and normative meth-
ods. I then discuss three objections and address the problem of how to bridge is and ought. In
the course of my analysis of three different bridge theories, I ultimately further develop the dual
nature thesis into a triadic nature thesis.
1. Introduction
The conception of legal scholarship as an academic discipline, with distinct re-
search questions, objects, and methods, is a highly contested issue. What exactly is
the proprium of legal scholarship? How can we construct the relations between legal
scholarship and other disciplines, most importantly moral and political philosophy,
sociology, and economics? “A picture of baffling diversity and perplexing inconsis-
tency” (Bodenheimer 1978, 204) exists beneath the glossy surface of our discipline:
Tossed to and fro between facticity and validity, political theory and legal theory today are
disintegrating into camps that hardly have anything more to say to one another. The tension
between normative approaches, which are constantly in danger of losing contact with social
reality, and objectivistic approaches, which screen out all normative aspects, can be taken as a
caveat against fixating on one disciplinary point of view. (Habermas 1996, 6)
Nonetheless, many scholars maintain that descriptive and normative inquiries in-
habit two different worlds of knowledge that we cannot hope to reconcile. There is a
significant need for a “reintegrative theory” (Dreier 2005, 221). The thesis I develop
in this article is that the triadic nature of law provides such a theory.
My new thesis that law has a triadic nature builds upon and further develops
Alexy’s (2010) dual nature thesis. Alexy advanced his dual nature thesis in a different
field, namely, the field concerned with the concept of law. I have already transferred
his conceptual thesis to the area of legal argumentation (Klatt 2015, 2016). In this
This is an open access article under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution-Non Commercial-No Derivs License, which
permits use and distribution in any medium, provided the original work is properly cited, the use is non-commercial and no
modifications or adaptations are made
381
Ratio Juris, Vol. 33, No. 4 © (2021) The Authors. Ratio Juris published by University of Bologna and John Wiley & Sons Ltd.
Integrative Jurisprudence
article, I endeavour to make a second transfer of this thesis, namely, to the problem of
the nature of legal scholarship (see also Nason 2013, 451–2).
The triadic nature of law leads me to the concept of integrative jurisprudence.
Integrative jurisprudence is a theory of legal scholarship that explicates the inter-
action of its various methods. Integrative jurisprudence holds that we must and
can bridge the rift between analytical, empirical, and normative methods by way of
synthesis (cf. Berman 1988, 779; Bodenheimer 1978, 204–5; Fechner 1962, 291–4; Hall
1958, 37–9). Integrative jurisprudence is in sharp contrast to all positions that see
descriptive and normative theories of law as radically disjunct. In this article, I want
to join forces with scholars who have castigated the “particularistic fallacy” (Fechner
1962, 53–86; Hall 1958, 25) of the prevailing restrictive theories of legal scholarship,
which monopolise one of the three methods at the cost of excluding the others.
In this article, I will understand “legal scholarship” as a single enterprise. I do
not intend to deny that it could also be understood as a plurality of enterprises. The
latter perspective arises when we consider the plurality of scholars and objectives of
academic enquiry. An intriguing taxonomy has been provided by Jakab (2011). The
diversity of legal cultures (Legrand 1996; Varga 2012) can influence different concep-
tions of legal scholarship and affect our judgements about the appropriate balance of
the three methods.
Nonetheless, I pursue the distinct question what these different approaches have
in common, and what unites them into a single enterprise. My aim is not to give a
complex descriptive account of the differences in legal scholarship. Instead, the very
point of my article is that these perspectives only grasp different sub-aspects of the
law. The question I address is what understanding of legal scholarship we arrive at
when we disregard the existing plurality of approaches. I concentrate on understand-
ing legal scholarship per se. I make a normative-analytical argument and claim that,
given the triadic nature of law, any scholarship that wants to get the full picture of
the law must be integrative. Attention to both the real and the ideal dimension and
their various sub-aspects is necessary in any enterprise that wants to understand
the law in its entirety. This leaves room for more narrow goals of inquiry which ac-
cordingly could focus on one or the other dimension of the law while neglecting
the others. While legal scholarship itself can be seen as a sociocultural phenomenon
(Engle Merry 2012; Kahn 1999; Nelken 2004), I engage in an analytical and normative
argument here.
2. The Dual Nature Thesis
Integrative jurisprudence presupposes a broader definition of law than that which is
usually adopted by each of the legal philosophical schools (Berman 1988, 781). The
dual nature thesis provides a starting point for such a broader definition. According
to the dual nature thesis, law consists of both a real, factual, authoritative, institu-
tional dimension as well as an ideal, critical dimension (Alexy 2010; Finnis 2014,
95–6; Jellinek 1921, 50; Wolf 1953, 20–1).
The ideal dimension of law stems from law’s claim to correctness (Alexy 2000).
Moral correctness is added to authoritative issuance and social efficacy as the third
element of a nonpositivist concept of law (Alexy 2010, 167). The claim to correctness
can only justify law’s ideal dimension if moral correctness exists at all—a premise
that the objection from moral irrationalism (Mackie 1977, 35) denies. Nonpositivists

To continue reading

Request your trial

VLEX uses login cookies to provide you with a better browsing experience. If you click on 'Accept' or continue browsing this site we consider that you accept our cookie policy. ACCEPT