Indigenous Rights before the Inter-American Court of Human Rights: a Call for a Pro Individual Interpretation

AuthorValerio de Oliveira Mazzuoli - Dilton Ribeiro
PositionFederal University of Mato Grosso, Brazil - Queen's University, Canada
Pages522-553
e Indonesian Journal of International & Comparative Law
ISSN: 2338-7602; E-ISSN: 2338-770X
http://www.ijil.org
© 2015 e Institute for Migrant Rights Press
522
I R 
 I-A C 
H R
A C   Pro IndIvIdual I
valErio dE olivEira Mazzuoli
Federal University of Mato Grosso, Brazil
E-mail: mazzuoli@ufmt.br
dilton ribEiro
Queen’s University, Canada
E-mail: 11drfr@queensu.ca
In its traditional conception, international law regulates relations between
sovereign states. is denition is challenged by current developments of
international law, especially in the area of human rights. e human person
is arguably a bearer of rights and duties under international law. However,
recognizing this individual legal personality is not enough. International bodies
and treaties need to acknowledge that individuals are subjects of international
law within a pluralistic world. In other words, the law of nations must crystalize
the idea that individuals are, with all their cultural dierences, subjects of
international law. e Inter-American Court of Human Rights recognizes
this view through its pro homine principle, which informs that human rights
instruments must seek the best possible protection for the human person. In
this interpretative framework, the Inter-American Court crystalized a body of
norms protecting indigenous rights and their cultural and historical backgrounds
within the general protection system of the American Convention. e extensive
Indigenous Rights before the Inter-American Court of Human Rights
523
Mazzuoli & Ribeiro
interpretation of rights articulates a new view on the individual legal personality.
Accordingly, this article seeks to understand this approach based on key decisions
of the Inter-American Court of Human Rights on indigenous cases.
Keywords: International Legal Personality, International Human Rights,
Indigenous Rights, Inter-American Court of Human Rights., Communitarianism
1. INTRODUCTION
e recognition of multiculturalism is unquestionably one of the most
signicant post-Second World War movements stemmed from the notion
of individual personality and human centrality. It is intrinsically linked to
the conception of the human person as a bearer of cultural characteristics
that are indispensable to a full and useful existence and that, consequent-
ly, must always be observed and respected. Political philosophy, especially
after the 1980s, made room for debate and the development of multiple
conceptions of multiculturalism. is debate, which soon later became
a concern of law and for lawyers, was strongly rooted in a divergence
between communitarians and liberals, and many questions and dierent
philosophical theories and perspectives still surround this discussion.1
1. In political philosophy, the debate on multiculturalism, which relates to a body of
ideas concerning legal accommodation and policies of ethnic diversity, is strongly
divided between the liberal and communitarian approaches. Liberals essentially
argue that individuals must be free to decide their own concept of good life and not
be constrained by any enforced or inherited condition. Conversely, communitarians
arm that every human being is connected through roles in social relations.
Kymlicka argues dierently by asserting that debates concerning individuals
and groups reach a consensus on liberalism and democracy, but disagree on the
interpretation of these principles in multiethnic and multinational societies. For a
general view on the concept of multiculturalism, on the liberal and communitarian
dichotomy, and on the characteristics or argument of multiculturalism, see, e.g.,
Charles Taylor, Interculturalism or Multiculturalism?, 38 P  S. C
413 (2012); John Arthur, Multiculturalism, in T O H 
P E (Hugh LaFollette ed., 2005); B P, R
M (2000); M M, M: A C
I (2012); Will Kymlicka, Multiculturalism in eory and Practice,
1 R C 3, 62 (2008) (Interview by Verena Risse & Martin Vezér);
W K, M: S, F,   F
(2012); T A R C  M (Duncan
The Indonesian Journal of International & Comparative Law Volume II Issue 3 (2015) at 522–54
Mazzuoli & Ribeiro
524
In the area of public policy, this topic bears considerable importance.
States and the international community as a whole look to better
accommodate national minorities and foreign individuals. Yet, they
face a modern world where technology facilitates immigration and with
territories that are occupied, peacefully or not, by peoples with diverse
cultural characteristics. ese characteristics go beyond the territorial
boundaries where these individuals reside and include a mosaic of features,
such as language, religion, philosophical views, and social conditions, that
constitute an intrinsic part of these individuals. Accordingly, this reality
generates heated public debates that are part of states’ political agenda,
especially after the Second World War.2
Due to its practical, political, legal and philosophical relevance,
multiculturalism is in a central stage in many dierent areas of study, such
as education, philosophy and political science. Furthermore, it is a key
aspect in debates concerning minorities, foreign population, immigration
and diversity in general.3 But paradoxically, multiculturalism is not a
Ivinson ed., 2010); W K, M C: A L
T  M R (1996); Jeremy Waldron, Minority Cultures and
the Cosmopolitan Alternative, 25 U. M. J. L. R 751 (1992); Michael
McDonald, Liberalism, Community, and Culture, 42 U. T L. J. 113 (1992);
Will Kymlicka, e Rights of Minority Cultures: Reply to Kukathas, 20 P. T
140 (1992); Chandran Kukathas, Cultural Rights Again: A Rejoinder to Kymlicka, 20
P. T 674 (1992); and C T, M: E
 P  R (1994).
2. Ideas about the accommodation of minorities in multiethnic, multinational
states have been part of policies for more than forty years. For a general view
on the debate on multiculturalism and human rights or public policy, see
M K, T P  I: L P T 
 D  D (2004); S S, J, G 
 P  M (2007); Will Kymlicka, L P
V: N, M Y C [P 
 V: N, M,  C] 30
(2003) [hereinafter K, L P]; S B, T C 
C: E  D   G E 59-67 (2002) [herein
after B, T C  C]; C J, M
 L 263-79 (Shabani Omid Payrow ed., 2007); Melissa Williams, Justice
Towards Groups: Political not Juridical, 23 P. T 75 (1995); and Michael
Murphy, e Limits of Culture in the Politics of Self-Determination, 1 E
367 (2001).
3. See supra note 2. See also J S-H, S D: R
 D C (2000); K. A A  A G,
C C: T P M  R (1998); A P,

To continue reading

Request your trial

VLEX uses login cookies to provide you with a better browsing experience. If you click on 'Accept' or continue browsing this site we consider that you accept our cookie policy. ACCEPT