Extremism, Free Speech and the Rule of Law: Evaluating the Compliance of Legislation Restricting Extremist Expressions with Article 19 ICCPR

AuthorAmy Shepherd
PositionMA(Cantab)(Law), LLM, Utrecht University, NL
Pages62-83
Amy Shepherd, ‘Extremism, Free Speech and the Rule of Law: Evaluating the
Compliance of Legislation Restricting Extremist Expressions with Article 19
ICCPR’ (2017) 33(85) Utrecht Journal of International and European Law
pp. 62–83, DOI: https://doi.org/10.5334/ujiel.405
UTRECHT JOURNAL OF
INTERNATIONAL AND EUROPEAN LAW
* MA(Cantab)(Law), LLM, Utrecht University, NL
RESEARCH ARTICLE
Extremism, Free Speech and the Rule of Law:
Evaluating the Compliance of Legislation
Restricting Extremist Expressions with Article 19
ICCPR
Amy Shepherd*
In the years since 9/11, international security discourse has heightened concerns around
extremism, positioning this as the key threat that States need to address in order to prevent and
combat terrorism. Politically, enactment of domestic legislation curtailing extremist expressions
has been internationally authorised and encouraged and in May 2016 the United Kingdom
(‘UK’), spearheading a liberal State trend towards rights-restrictive approaches to extrem-
ism, announced its intention to enact legislation imposing a range of civil sanctions on those
publicly expressing extremist views. But laws such as this restrict the core democratic right
to freedom of expression and so must comply with the tripartite requirements for restrictions
enshrined in Article 19(3) of the International Covenant on Civil and Political Rights (‘ICCPR’) to
be legitimate. Using the UK to dynamically exemplify the issues, this paper assesses the manner
in which the laws curtailing extremist expressions comply with international human rights law.
Keywords: freedom of expression; terrorism; extremism; counter-terrorism; counter-extremism;
Article 19 International Covenant on Civil and Political Rights; ICCPR
‘The question is not whether we will be extremists but what kind of extremists we will be. Will we
be extremists for hate, or will we be extremists for love? Will we be extremists for the preservation of
injustice, or will we be extremists for the cause of justice?’
Martin Luther King, Letters from a Birmingham Jail, 1963
‘The poisonous messages of extremists must not be allowed to drown out the voices of the moderate
majority’.
UK Government, Prevent Strategy, 2011
Introduction
Since September 2001 the international community has witnessed a proliferation of legislation ostensibly
designed and intended to protect citizens from individuals and groups in the process of and prepared to
use acts of violence against society. As part of this allegedly protective movement numerous States have bol-
stered, enacted or proposed to enact laws focused on outlawing so-called extremist speech, drawing, whether
explicitly or implicitly, a direct line from people publicly expressing ‘extreme’ views to their committing acts
of terrorist violence. Such laws, however, have concerning human rights implications, and whilst banning
or punishing extremism might be expected of authoritarian governments, the scope of UN-led, USA and
Shepherd 63
EU counter-extremism initiatives indicates a concerning trend of liberal States embracing opportunities to
impose severe restrictions on ‘extreme’ speech.1
Labelling views and opinions as extremist is far from new2 but 9/11 can be empirically identified as the
major catalyst for the contemporary resurgence of the idea of extremism as a threat. It was through the
aftermath of 9/11 that extremism became embedded in domestic and international discourse and practice as
the predominant ‘root’ of terrorism. Broadly speaking, terrorists pursue political or societal change through
violent means. Ideological motive distinguishes terrorism from other criminal violence and willingness to
kill or harm civilians to achieve their ends marks terrorists out from other political activists. ‘Traditional’
counter-terrorism activities, however, focused only on securing and protecting against extant violent
plots; strategies sought neither to understand the ‘root causes’ of terrorism nor do anything to address the
underlying conditions creating terrorists.3 11 September 2001 changed this. The events of that day there-
after linked the commission of terrorist atrocities with belief in extreme doctrine and drove forward a new
global approach to counter-terrorism that fixated on combating harmful expressions of ‘extreme’ ideolo-
gies.4 This new approach to counter-terrorism gradually, subtly but inexorably, bound terrorism ever-tighter
with the idea of ‘extremism’. Without ever precisely defining ‘extremism’ the publicised imperative of States
became to defeat this ‘evil’, almost thereby reducing battling actual terrorist violence to a secondary respon-
sibility.5 This approach was spurred on by the UN, which in 2015 firmly established ‘eliminating extremist
speech’ as an urgent and critical goal on the worldwide political agenda.6
In the wake of the globalised ‘war on terror’ counter-extremism has become a widespread, high-agenda
policy aim, particularly for liberal States.7 Despite this politicised focus on extremism, however, domes-
tic legislatures have largely skirted round implementing explicit laws prohibiting or penalising extremist
speech: freedom of expression sanctions on extremism have more commonly been imposed by defining
extremism in policy documents then suppressing identified extremist ideologies through targeted applica-
tion of laws against hate speech and criminal offences such as ‘inciting terrorism’.8 Notably however, the
UK, spearheading the liberal State approach and building on its 2015 ‘Counter-Extremism Strategy’ which
defined extremism as ‘vocal or active opposition to fundamental British values including democracy, the rule
of law, individual liberty, mutual respect and tolerance of different faiths and beliefs, as well as calling for the
deaths of members of the armed forces’,9 is currently in the process of enacting primary legislation explic-
itly referencing extremism. The UK ‘Counter-Extremism and Safeguarding Bill’ announced in the Queen’s
Speech of 18 May 2016 is expected to codify the above definition of extremism and impose a range of mainly
civil measures directed towards eliminating allegedly dangerous extremist speech from public dialogue.10
1
Initiatives summarised within UNHRC, ‘Report of the Special Rapporteur on the promotion and protection of human rights and
fundamental freedoms while countering terrorism’ (22 February 2016) UN Document A/HRC/31/65, 8–9. See also (n 7).
2
See Amos N Guiora, Tolerating Intolerance: The Price of Protecting Extremism (OUP 2014) Chapter 1 for detailed discussion on the
historical status of extremism.
3
See Bruce Hoffman, Inside Terrorism (Columbia University Press 2006) Chapter 1 for a detailed historical analysis of terrorism and
counter-terrorism.
4
ibid 37; Conor Gearty, Can Human Rights Survive? (CUP 2000) 111.
5
See particularly UNSC Res 2178 (24 September 2014) UN Doc S/RES/2178/2014; UK Government, ‘Counter-Extremism Strategy’
(2015) Command Paper 9148, 5.
6
UNHRC (n 1); UNHRC, ‘Human Rights and preventing and countering violent extremism’ (1 October 2015) UN Doc A/HRC/30/L.25/
Rev.1; UNGA, ‘Plan of Action to Prevent Violent Extremism’ (24 December 2015) UN Doc A/70/674; See also statement by UN
Secretary-General, Ban Ki-Moon, ‘Uniting to Prevent Violent Extremism’ (15 January 2016) .huffingtonpost.com/
ban-kimoon/uniting-to-prevent-violen_b_8994150.html> accessed 25 July 2017; Colum Lynch, ‘UN Seeks more than $100 mil-
lion to tackle violent extremism’ Foreign Policy (8 March 2017) 7/03/08/u-n-seeks-more-than-100-
million-to-tackle-violent-extremism/> accessed 9 June 2017.
7
In addition to the UK see e.g. Australia, ‘Living Safe Together Strategy’ <http://www.livingsafetogether.gov.au/pages/home.aspx>;
Canada, ‘Counter-Extremism Strategy’;
aspx>; USA, ‘Department of State and USAID Joint Strategy on Countering Violent Extremism’
organization/257913.pdf>; Denmark, ‘A common and safe future
4AE8-99EB-928753EFC1F8/0/a_common_and_safe_future_danish_action_plan_to_prevent_extremism.pdf> accessed 9 June
2017.
8
Australia, ‘Living Safe Together Strategy’ (n 7); see also Law Library of Congress Reports
extremism/index.php>; Counter-Extremism Project accessed 9 June 2017.
9
UK ‘Counter-Extremism Strategy’ (n 5) 1.
10 Her Majesty’s most gracious speech to both Houses of Parliament at the State Opening of Parliament (18 May 2016) 49–50
www.gov.uk/government/speeches/queens-speech-2016> accessed 25 July 2017. Intention to proceed with counter-extremism
legislation as a priority has been reiterated by the Conservative party in the recent UK general election: see, ‘Forward Together:
Our Plan for a Stronger Britain and a Prosperous Future, Conservative Party Manifesto 2017’ 38, 55 .conser vatives.
com/manifesto> accessed 25 July 2017. With additional plans to establish a statutory ‘Commission for Countering Extremism’
Extremism, Free Speech and the Rule of Law64
Whatever form States’ extremism legislation takes, laws that restrict the right to freedom of expression
citing an imperative of ‘countering extremism’ are of questionable compatibility with international human
rights law.11 Freedom of expression is universally considered to be one of the most fundamental and
important civil and political rights, deserving of particularly strong protection.12 It is well-established that
the right, enshrined in the Universal Declaration on Human Rights, the International Covenant on Civil
and Political Rights (‘ICCPR’) and a range of regional conventions and declarations,13 encompasses the right
to hold, express and receive a very broad range of views and ideas, including those that are unpalatable,
controversial and shocking.14 It is further clear that though not absolute the right to freedom of expres-
sion may only be restricted in very narrow circumstances.15 In all cases restrictions must be enacted in
accordance with law, serve a legitimate purpose and be necessary to achieve that identified purpose.16
In view of these high standards, imposing civil or criminal penalties on people expressing extrem-
ist views and ideas is potentially very problematic. In particular, it is doubtful whether any sufficiently
precise definition of extremism can be constructed to satisfy legality; though governments are empowered
and expected to protect their people from harm it is debatable whether curtailing extremist speech serves
any legitimate objective; and, the need to eliminate a portion of free speech to protect at all is very much
open for discussion.
The UN Special Rapporteur on the Promotion and Protection of Human Rights and Fundamental Freedoms
while Countering Terrorism (‘UN Terrorism Rapporteur’) re-stressed in early 2016 the need for legislation
pertaining to extremism to comply with international human rights law.17 However, whether or not it can
theoretically do so presently remains an open question. This paper addresses that gap, investigating the
considerations and concerns that domestic legal reliance on the concept of extremism raises in connection
with international human rights law. It examines extremism in connection with the right to freedom of
expression and asks from a theoretical perspective whether domestic legislation restricting extremist speech
does or can comply with the tripartite test for restrictions set out in Article 19(3) ICCPR. Systematic analysis
exploring the facets of extremism explicitly within the framework of international human rights law has not
to date been undertaken; this paper’s detailed exploration of the legal facets of extremism consequently
informs and enriches both prior and future related discourse on counter-terrorism, counter-extremism and
freedom of expression generally.
The paper’s structure reflects the Article 19(3) criteria: the first section investigates the compliance of
extremism legislation with the principle of legality, the second scrutinises the legitimate purposes extrem-
ism legislation might serve and the third queries whether or how extremism legislation can satisfy the strict
test of necessity. As a whole, the paper adopts a black-letter interpretive approach, testing the fit of the
content and rationale of domestic laws referencing extremism with the established precepts of international
law. In view of the nuanced legal, political and socio-legal dynamics involved in extremism, the paper draws
upon an array of multi-disciplinary sources to interpret international law and inform its analysis. Further,
as the relationship between national and international law can be more easily analysed in abstract when
referring to a specific legal order, the paper grounds its theoretical discussion by using UK definitions and
documents to dynamically exemplify the real-world application of its arguments and conclusions. The UK is
selected for illustrative purposes because it has a detailed counter-extremism policy which is already acting
forming part of the Queen’s Speech (21 June 2017) .gov.uk/government/speeches/queens-speech-2017>; see
George Parker,‘Theresa May lays out plans to tackle domestic extremism’ Financial Times (27 May 2017)
content/537f435a-42eb-11e7-ab92-4c27fbc26eed> accessed 21 June 2017.
11 Consider e.g. ARTICLE 19, ‘Kyrgyzstan: Law on Countering Extremist Activity’ (December 2015)
files/medialibrary/38221/Kyrgyzstan-Extremism-LA-Final.pdf>; Russia: misuse of anti-extremism legislation monitored by SOVA
Center for Information and Analysis: accessed 21 June 2017, critiqued in US State
Department, ‘2015 Human Rights Report’ (13 April 2016) s 2(a) <http://www.state.gov/j/drl/rls/hrrpt/2015/eur/252893.htm>
accessed 21 June 2017; Jack Moore, ‘Erdogan to Expand Turkish Extremism Laws to Target Critics’ Democracy Chronicles (16 March
2016) accessed 9 June 2017.
12 UNGA Res 59(1) (14 December 1946) UN Doc A/RES/59(I).
13 Full details of international standards on freedom of expression
Standards.aspx> accessed 9 June 2017.
14 Handyside v. UK App No 5493/72 (ECtHR, 7 December 1976) 49.
15 UNHRC, ‘General Comment No 34’ (12 September 2011) UN Doc CCPR/C/GC/34, 2, 36.
16 International Covenant on Civil and Political Rights (adopted 16 December 1966, entered into force 23 March 1976) 999 UNTS 171,
art 19(3).
17 UN Terrorism Rapporteur 2016 Report (n 1) 33.
Shepherd 65
as a benchmark for other liberal States18 and its international political standing together with the intense
deliberations of its legislative process may particularly give its Counter-Extremism Bill (if and once enacted)
a wider legitimising and emboldening impact in both liberal and proto-liberal States.19 Though primarily
referencing a European jurisdiction, the paper similarly chooses to frame its analysis within Article 19 ICCPR
rather than Article 10 of the European Convention on Human Rights (‘ECHR’) in order to highlight the
worldwide application of the paper’s discussion and conclusions.20
It is acknowledged that the State approaches, academic literature and the UN’s discourse on security,
terrorism and extremism on which it relies are generally infused by terrorism and extremism as ‘Islamist’.
However, as it unpacks the layers and facets of extremism this paper takes care not to limit its analysis to
any particular extremist ideology. Referring variously to ‘extremist speech’ and ‘extremist expressions’, the
paper at all times adopts the definition of ‘expression’ formulated by the UN Human Rights Committee in
its General Comment No. 34.21 It is assumed that all forms of extremist expression encompass a political
element, even if modally amounting to creative endeavour.
The Challenge of Legally Restricting Extremist Expressions
Ascertaining whether domestic legislation which prohibits under civil law provisions or criminally penalises
public expressions of extremism does or could comply with the requirements of Article 19(3) ICCPR first
requires asking whether such laws are or could be enacted ‘in accordance with law’. Crucially, though the
three limbs of Article 19(3) collectively concern the rule of law, discussion of the object of and need for
fundamental rights restrictions a priori requires the terms of restrictive legislation to be internally lawful.
Legality Under The ICCPR
It is well-established in international law that laws must be clear, accessible and formulated with sufficient
precision to enable individuals to regulate their conduct accordingly.22 It contravenes the principle of legal-
ity to prohibit or sanction conduct without a clear definition of what exactly the law is targeting.23 The level
of precision required of laws depends on the type of law in question, the field it is designed to cover and
the number and status of those to whom it is addressed.24 Laws must not be arbitrary or unreasonable and
should contain adequate safeguards against the illegal or abusive imposition of restrictions on fundamental
rights through their implementation.25 Legality is further measured by how effective laws are in protecting
the right to non-discrimination: laws that inherently discriminate breach Article 26 ICCPR.26 In respect of
freedom of expression, unclear legal restrictions have a particularly pernicious effect, with individuals tend-
ing towards excessive self-censorship in the absence of clarity over where exactly the boundary to illegality
lies.27 The fundamental importance of free speech for democracy therefore demands that laws infringing
18 See Simon Hooper, ‘UK Prevent Strategist to build counter-extremism programmes in Central Asia’ Middle-East Eye (23 May
2017) .middleeasteye.net/news/home-office-prevent-strategist-build-counter-extremism-programmes-central-
asia-1883821989> accessed 9 June 2017; See also (n 7).
19 See UK free expression organisation’s joint statement, ‘Planned new UK laws on extremism threaten free speech’ (18 May 2016)
<https://www.article19.org/resources.php/resource/38380/en/joint-statement:-planned-new-uk-laws-on-extremism-threaten-
free-speech> accessed 9 June 2017.
20 Framing the analysis within Article 10 ECHR would make little practical difference to the development of theory. The ICCPR and
ECHR were both designed to give effect to the Universal Declaration on Human Rights so are linguistically aligned and largely cor-
respond with one another in substantive content. Jurisprudence interpreting Article 10 ECHR has weight in interpreting Article
19 ICCPR and vice versa. Focusing on Article 19 ICCPR for present purposes, however, helps to contextualise extremism as a global
issue and aims to limit any criticism of regional bias.
21 General Comment No 34 (n 15) 12.
22 Sunday Times v. UK App No 6538/74 (ECtHR, 26 April 1979) 49.
23 Per UN NGO Joint Submission, ‘Initiatives to ‘counter and prevent violent extremism’ raise serious human rights concerns’ (4 Febru-
ary 2016) UN Doc A/HRC/31/NGO/X, supplemented by a joint letter to the UN High Commissioner for Human Rights, Zeid Ra’ad
Al Hussein, undated but issued in advance of the panel discussion on Preventing Violent Extremism at the 31st Session of the HRC
March 2016 .article19.org/data/files/Joint_Letter_to_High_Commissioner_PVE.pdf> accessed 9 June 2017.
24 Hashman & Harrup v. UK App No 25594/94 (ECtHR, 25 November 1999) 31.
25 UN Commission on Human Rights, ‘Siracusa Principles on the Limitation and Derogation Provisions in the ICCPR’ (28 September
1984) UN Doc E/CN.4/1985/4, Principles 16 and 18. These principles were formulated by academics and experts at an interna-
tional NGO conference and adopted by the UN at the request of the Netherlands to ensure interpretation of the ICCPR remained
consistent with its object and purpose.
26 General Comment No 34 (n 15) 26.
27 See Amnesty International, ‘Report on Rwanda’s Laws on ‘Genocide Ideology’ and ‘Sectarianism’ (2010) Index No. AFR/47/005/
2010, 27.
Extremism, Free Speech and the Rule of Law66
upon this right be drafted particularly narrowly and precisely28 and that restrictions be enshrined in positive
legislation.29
The ICCPR’s structure closely aligns the general protection of freedom of expression under Article 19
with the protective directive of Article 20(2), making this provision equally important in any discussion on
freedom of expression. Article 20(2) puts States under an active duty to prohibit ‘advocacy of national, racial
or religious hatred that constitutes incitement to discrimination, hostility or violence’. Jurisprudence of the
European Court of Human Rights (‘ECtHR’) has clarified that there is a dynamic component to ‘incitement’.
It is not enough to express accord with a hostile, discriminatory or violent worldview, even passionately; to
amount to ‘incitement’ statements must positively intend to encourage or solicit other people to engage in
hostility, discrimination or acts of violence.30 Despite Article 20(2) definitively requiring law-making, domes-
tic measures implementing its strictures must equally comply with the tripartite test for permissible restric-
tions set out in Article 19(3).31
Further, whether seeking to restrict speech under Article 19(3) or Article 20(2) a close nexus between the
relevant expression and a risk of it causing harm is vital for legality. The UN Rabat Plan of Action32 recom-
mends that in assessing whether speech should be criminalised by States as ‘incitement’ regard should be
had to the general context, the speaker, his/her intent, the content of the message, its form, the extent of
the speech at issue and the likelihood of harm occurring, including its imminence. These factors are also
generally useful as a point of reference when defining ‘harmful’ speech. To determine whether speech advo-
cates hate the Rabat Plan encourages States to refer to ARTICLE 19’s Camden Principles, which define hatred
as ‘intense and irrational emotions of opprobrium, enmity and detestation’.33
Drawing this guidance together in the context of extremism, it may be briefly concluded that legally
restricting extremist free expression requires constructing a narrow definition of extremism that identifies
precisely what it entails and links it causally to hate and/or violence yet does not target, either deliberately
or inadvertently, any particular group or individual. That established, this paper now questions whether and
how formulation of such a definition could be possible.
Legislating Against Extremism
As identified above, legislation restricting extremist speech needs to refer to a definition of extremism which
targets with precision an identified harm. Terminology is important not only to satisfy legality; language
chosen here also impacts on the second and third limbs of Article 19(3). The objective that restrictions on
extremist speech may be said to serve and the need to restrict extremists’ freedom of expression will both
be affected by the way in which extremism is defined. Put another way, it may be extremely difficult or
impossible to satisfy any of the limbs of Article 19(3) if ‘extremism’ is obliquely framed in porous and mul-
titudinous terms.
The UK Joint Human Rights Committee emphasised in their scrutiny of the Counter-Extremism Bill that
extremism is a tricky concept to pin down.34 However, politically, domestic and international approaches to
extremism are predicated on it being a necessary precursor to terrorism. Consequently, to assess what, if any,
terminology can accurately capture the threat of extremism without also being illegitimately broad, vague
or discriminatory, this paper first seeks to understand how contemporary conceptions of extremism have
come to be permeated by an enduring link between extremists and terrorists.
28 General Comment No 34 (n 15) 22, 25, 46.
29 ibid 24.
30 Surek No. 1 v. Turkey App No 26682/95 (ECtHR, 8 July 1999) 62–63; Robert Faurisson v. France, Comm No 550/1993 (8 November
1996) UN Doc CCPR/C/58/D/550/1993 6, 9; contrast Gunduz v. Turkey App No 35071/97 (ECtHR, 4 September 2003) 51.
31 Ross v. Canada Comm No 736/97 (18 October 2000) UN Doc CCPR/C/70/D/736/1997 11.1.
32 UN, Rabat Plan of Action on the prohibition of advocacy of national, racial or religious hatred that constitutes incitement to dis-
crimination, hostility or violence (5 October 2012) .un.org/en/preventgenocide/adviser/pdf/Rabat_draft_outcome.
pdf> accessed 25 July 2017. This comprises conclusions and recommendations emanating from an inter-regional process involving
four OHCHR expert workshops.
33 ARTICLE 19, ‘Camden Principles on Freedom of Expression and Equality’ (2009) Principle 12. Prepared on the basis of discussions
by experts in freedom of expression and equality these represent a progressive interpretation of international standards.
34 UK Parliament Joint Committee on Human Rights, ‘Counter-Extremism Report’ (22 July 2016) .publications.parliament.
uk/pa/jt201617/jtselect/jtrights/105/10502.htm?utm_source=105&utm_medium=fullbullet&utm_campaign=modulereports>
accessed 25 July 2017. The UK government has not to date formulated any workable definition of extremism; see letter to the Com-
mittee on Human Rights by then Home Secretary Amber Rudd MP dated 27 February 2017 in response to a direct question from
the committee chair on this point
committee/legislative-scrutiny/parliament-2015/extremism-bill/> accessed 9 June 2017.
Shepherd 67
Extremism and Terrorism
A gradual but inexorable shift in State perceptions of terrorism since September 2001 transformed the ‘ter-
rorist’ into a morally charged being. Although the term ‘terrorism’ had held a pejorative connotation long
before 9/11,35 it was until that devastating day mainly engaged simply to describe a tactic used by political
militants vying for regime change.36 It took the advent of ‘war on terror’ parlance to fully embed ‘terrorist’
as a marker of identity and imbue the title with truly foul connotations.37 To define an act as one of terror
is now to condemn it as utterly immoral.38 Persons labelled as terrorist are largely characterised as evil39 and
the label has permanence: once categorised, terrorists are deemed so regardless of and in spite of any future
action, inaction or voiced opinion.40
The post-9/11 transformation of terrorism from (broadly) an illegal act committed by an actor with no
particular moral status to an immoral act committed by an immoral actor first enabled and later encour-
aged counter-terrorism strategies to extend beyond foiling terrorist plots and delve into the ‘root causes’ of
terrorism.41 Additionally, once conceptually terrorism became about ‘bad people’ it was a relatively straight-
forward shift for counter-terrorism discourse to come to regard terrorists as the maturation of ‘extreme’
people; the violent end result of people intensely imbibing ‘extreme’ doctrine. A more nuanced approach to
terrorism taking account of the array of political and socio-economic factors feeding into the phenomenon
has eventually gained a certain amount of ground in liberal States42 but initially the importance and impact
of wider circumstances as markers of the likelihood of terrorism was generally diminished amid the charged
political atmosphere post-9/11. The ‘problem’ of extremism was awarded a place of predominance in secu-
rity discourse which it has always since retained.43
Post-9/11 embedding of extremism underpinning terrorism also linked extremism with ‘radicalisation’.
Focusing on the dangers of extremist ideologies supposes that individuals develop extremist political views
then seek to put them into practice. It emphasises individual choice in taking violent, terrorist action and
implies that individuals ‘radicalised’ through the process of receiving and adopting extremist views vol-
untarily join terrorist movements, finding in them ideological congruence, rather than being recruited or
coerced.44 The aim of post-9/11 ‘counter-extremism’ was thus conceived as being to prevent ‘radicalisation’,
cutting the threat of terrorism off at its source. ‘Counter-extremism’ measures intruding on civil freedoms
were simply cast as eliminating sooner the risk of violence. Nonetheless, despite the rise and continuance
of a perceptible international fixation on extremism and ‘radicalisation’ as the crux of terrorism the valid-
ity of any direct linear progression from expression to action has been and continues to be stridently cri-
tiqued. Terrorism studies freely admit the difficulties in explaining terrorism with reference to any singular
concept,45 the UN Terrorism Rapporteur in early 2016 again decried the existence of a ‘fixed trajectory’ to
radical violence46 and an (albeit isolated) recent study has, slightly controversially, indicated that experi-
ence of ordinary criminal violence is a more significant indicator of future terrorist action than holding or
35 Hoffman (n 3) 23.
36 ibid. Also Gearty (n 3) 114–123. See also (n 37).
37 Gearty (n 3) 111; Hoffman (n 3) 32; Crenshaw (1981) cited through Kundnani, ‘A Decade Lost: Rethinking Radicalisation and
Extremism’ (2015) Claystone Independent Think-Tank Report 14.
38 Gearty (n 3) 113, 122; Kenan Malik, ‘Out of Bounds’ (2008) 37 Index on Censorship 145.
39 Although not always; see Stanford Encyclopedia on Philosophy, ‘Terrorism’ (23 February 2015) 1.2.2
entries/terrorism/> accessed 9 June 2017. There was also some notion of terrorists being evil pre-9/11 as without discussion of
‘root causes’ terrorism was perceived as being inexplicably evil isolated events. See e.g. Herman and Sullivan (1989) cited through
Dawn Rothe and Stephen L Muzzatti, ‘Enemies Everywhere: Terrorism, Moral Panic and US Civil Society’ (2004) 12 Critical Criminol-
ogy 331.
40 Gearty (n 3) 112.
41 Some initial resistance to discussion of ‘root causes’ stemmed from commentators who claimed that this was merely an effort to
excuse and justify the killing of innocent civilians. See e.g. Neumann (2008) cited through Kundnani (n 37) 10.
42 E.g. UK Government, ‘Prevent Strategy’ (2011) Command Paper 8092.
43 Consider particularly UNSC Res 1624 (14 September 2005) UN Doc S/RES/1624/2005:
‘. . . Deeply concerned that incitement of terrorist acts motivated by extremism and intolerance poses a serious and
growing danger to the enjoyment of humanrights, threatens the social and economic development of all States, under-
mines global stability and prosperity, and must be addressed urgently and proactively by the United Nations and all
States. . . ’.
44 Malik (n 38) 145–146; Royal United Services Institute, ‘Drivers of Violent Extremism: Hypotheses and Literature Review’
(October 2015) 10 .uk/pdf/outputs/Misc_Gov/Drivers_of_Radicalisation_Literature_Review.pdf> accessed 9
June 2017.
45 Nafeez Ahmed, ‘The astonishingly crap science of counter-terrorism’ Insurge Intelligence (17 March 2016)
insurge-intelligence/the-astonishingly-crap-science-of-counter-extremism-65810f8ac8e6#.i08vgya0c> accessed 9 June 2017.
46 UN Terrorism Rapporteur 2016 Report (n 1) 15.
Extremism, Free Speech and the Rule of Law68
promoting any extremist ideology.47 Honing in on extremism in terrorist theory thus largely or effectively
ignores the ‘complex picture of social, cultural, economic, political and psychological factors which all con-
verge in a negative dynamic to produce those who commit terrorist acts’.48
Consequently, though extremism may be politically viewed through the prism of terrorism, as a matter of
law Article 19(3)’s requirement of legality is not automatically thereby met. Even accepting that empirical
evidence points to extremism as being a partial contributor to terrorism, expressions of extremism generally
include no direct calls to terrorist action; these would in any event fall within the strictures of Article 20(2)
ICCPR and be prima facie outlawed. In fact, when recalling the particular importance of narrowness where
restrictions upon freedom of expression are concerned, it is arguable that only expressions of extremism
meeting the threshold of Article 20(2) do or could comprise the causal nexus to harm necessary for legal-
ity: in the absence of linear progression from speech to action, without incitement even the most vitriolic
statement of extremism is arguably too far removed from any eventual violence for legality to be satisfied.
Nonetheless, liberal approaches to counter-extremism implicitly reject any notion of ‘non-violent extrem-
ism’. Despite blind assertions to the contrary, liberal States’ counter-extremism is underpinned by an asser-
tion that even if ‘extremists’ do not always become terrorists, extremism ‘can create an atmosphere conducive
to terrorism and can popularise views which terrorists then exploit’.49 Exemplifying this, the UK Counter-
Extremism Strategy identifies extremists as ‘carefully portray[ing] violence as inevitable in achieving the
desired end state required by their ideology’ and/or using rhetoric characterised by violent language.50 This
indirect causal connection between extremism and terrorism could potentially provide a definitional nexus
with harm sufficient to satisfy Article 19(3)’s legality criteria. Schmid, having researched extensively into ter-
rorism and extremism definitions, considers it naïve and dangerous to assume that one can hold extremist
beliefs but not be inclined to use extremist (i.e. violent) methods to realise them when the opportunity pre-
sents itself: he argues that even ostensibly not-violent organisations can act as ‘stepping stones’ to violence
as both are ultimately party to a common agenda.51 Extrapolating from the theory of fear speech posited by
Buyse,52 which notes that conflicts escalate when parties use both speech and action in tactics of increasing
harshness, it is feasible to reason that extremist expressions referring to violence, especially where under-
pinned by values running counter to the tenets of liberal democracy, could have a ‘conflict escalating’ effect,
increasing the likelihood of terrorist violence occurring. Indirect causality must be approached with caution
though: the more stretched the link between extremism and terrorism becomes, the greater strength there
is to arguments that only where incitement exists and speech becomes categorised under Article 20(2)
might legality be satisfied.
Furthermore, even if extremism can theoretically be legally related to terrorism, the connection depends
upon a fixed conception that the key marker of extremist ideologies justifying restriction of fundamental
rights is anti-liberal sentiment (consider the UK’s contrasting of extremism with ‘British values’ – a phrase
open to question and interpretation but reasonably understood generally to encompass the underpinning
values of liberal society); however, as a stand-alone term extremism is a nebulous concept embracing a host
of non-mainstream views. Notably, use of the term ‘ecological extremists’ has increased exponentially with
the rise of conservation activism to describe the views held by a certain cohort of environmental and animal
rights protesters. These political ‘extremists’ actively embrace the label for their own reasons but though
they may be ‘extremists’ in the sense that they are arguably equally ‘absolutists, locked in on their particular
viewpoint, largely incapable of understanding, if not intolerant, of other perspectives’ and ‘having an ideol-
ogy that is ‘the truth’ to be defended at all costs’,53 in pursuit of their goals ‘ecological extremists’ neither aim
47 Manni Crone, ‘Radicalization revisited: violence, politics and the skills of the body’ (2016) 92 Journal of International Affairs
587–604. See also Coral Dando, ‘What science can reveal about the psychological profiles of terrorists’ The Conversation (26 May
2017) accessed
9 June 2017, which highlights that some recent research suggests that the biggest marker of terrorists is abnormal moral cognition,
with an over-reliance on outcomes; a psychological ‘quest for significance’ may be ‘an important driver of extremist behaviour’.
48 Ömer Taşpınar, ‘Fighting Radicalism, not ‘Terrorism’: Root Causes of an International Actor Redefined’ (2006) 29 SAIS Review
76–77.
49 UK Government, ‘Revised Prevent Duty Guidance’ (16 July 2015) .gov.uk/government/uploads/system/uploads/
attachment_data/file/445977/3799_Revised_Prevent_Duty_Guidance__England_Wales_V2-Interactive.pdf> 3 accessed 9 June
2017.
50 UK Counter-Extremism Strategy (n 5) 10–11.
51 Alex P Schmid, ‘Violent and Non-Violent Extremism: Two Sides of the Same Coin?’ (2014) ICCT Research Paper 2, 3, 19, 20.
52 Antoine Buyse, ‘Words of Violence: ‘Fear Speech’ or How Violent Conflict Escalation Relates to the Freedom of Expression’ (2014)
36 Human Rights Quarterly 779–797.
53 Guiora (n 2) 39.
Shepherd 69
to destroy the democratic order nor advocate hate or support violence – except perhaps in terms of property
destruction.54 Particularly where seeking to restrict expressions broader than incitement, therefore, the term
‘extremism’ needs careful further explication to ensure laws do not inadvertently net ‘extremists’ such as
these whose ideas and motives have no connection to the scourge of global terrorism.
Dening and Codifying Extremism
Even within the terrorism paradigm, the question remains: can any satisfactorily narrow and targeted legal
definition of extremism be formulated to meet Article 19(3)’s legality criteria? Extremism has no agreed
definition in international law. In fact, despite the term ‘violent extremism’ forming the crux of the UN
General Assembly’s 2015 ‘Plan of Action to Prevent Violent Extremism’ this document rather worryingly
opens by asserting that even this arguably more limited formulation eludes definition.55 The addition of
‘violent’ to extremism provides no de facto clarity. Delegating to States the responsibility for construct-
ing individual definitions of extremism, the Plan of Action gives no guidance on the substantive content
to extremism, merely reminding States that they must enact law that complies with international human
rights standards.56 Reiterating this warning, representatives from the UN, the Organization for Security and
Co-operation in Europe (‘OSCE’), the Organisation of American States (‘OAS’) and the African Commission
on Human and Peoples’ Rights (‘ACHPR’) jointly stated in May 2016 that unless given an appropriately exact
definition the concept of extremism should not be used as the basis for restricting freedom of expression.57
This supplemented an earlier joint statement stipulating that domestic laws should not employ such vague
terms as ‘glorifying’, ‘promoting’ or ‘supporting’ extremism.58
The UN and regional bodies may legitimately be trying to respect domestic sovereignty in refusing to
codify extremism in international law and/or proffering no detail on its substantive content, but for States
seeking to ensure that extremism legislation is enacted and implemented in compliance with international
law the lack of international clarity on what is meant when referring to extremism is both unhelpful and
problematic. ‘Success’ in fighting the global threat of terrorism through employing extremism restrictions
is fatally undermined by domestic definitions of extremism that are ill-harmonised; formulated and applied
disjointedly according to what States discretely perceive as threatening. A joint NGO submission to the UN
in February 2016 outlined severe concerns that State-generated definitions of extremism presently capture
angry but non-threatening expressions of unpopular ideas and government criticism along with truly dan-
gerous expressions of bigoted and violent ideologies.59 An international-level definition of extremism would
thus be both appropriate and beneficial: material specification of universally applicable markers of extrem-
ism in international law could vitally help to prevent abusive local language and align domestic laws that
are, at least ostensibly, premised on targeting a singular, globalised harm.
Whether or not defining at an international level, however, translating extremism into adequate and appro-
priate legal terminology still presents a Herculean task.60 The definitional issues highlighted by NGOs in their
joint submission to the UN61 are not limited to authoritarian States; as noted above, even the reference to
‘British values’ in the UK definition of extremism is potentially problematic, becoming imbued with differ-
ent content depending on who is articulating the phrase, where and when, as well as arguably lending itself
to allow an interpretation of extremism entirely devoid of any ultimate connection to violence. Some NGOs
have opined that the very inability to articulate clearly and precisely what unlawful extremism encompasses
54 Elżbieta Posłuszna, Environmental and Animal Rights Extremism, Terrorism and National Security (Butterworth-Heinemann 2015)
3–5.
55 UN Plan of Action to Prevent Violent Extremism (n 6) 1.
56 ibid 2.
57 UN Special Rapporteur on Freedom of Opinion and Expression, OSCE Representative on Freedom of the Media, OAS Special Rap-
porteur on Freedom of Expression and ACHPR Special Rapporteur on Freedom of Expression and Access to Information, ‘Joint
Declaration on Freedom of Expression and Countering Violent Extremism’ (3 May 2016) .article19.org/data/files/
medialibrary/38355/Joint-Declaration-on-Freedom-of-Expression-and-Countering-Violent-Extremism-2016.pdf> accessed 9 June
2017.
58 UN Special Rapporteur on Freedom of Opinion and Expression, OSCE Representative on Freedom of the Media, OAS Special Rappor-
teur on Freedom of Expression and ACHPR Special Rapporteur on Freedom of Expression and Access to Information, ‘Joint Declara-
tion on defamation of religions, and anti-terrorism and anti-extremism legislation’ (10 December 2008) 9.
org/resources.php/resource/3058/en/joint-declaration-on-defamation-of-religions,-and-anti-terrorism,-and-anti-extremism-
legislation> accessed 9 June 2017. See also General Comment No 34 (n 15) 46.
59 UN, Joint Submission (n 23).
60 See Alan Travis, ‘Cameron terror strategy runs aground on definition of extremism’ The Guardian (3 May 2016) .the-
guardian.com/politics/2016/may/03/david-cameron-terror-strategy-definition-extremism> accessed 9 June 2017.
61 See (n 57).
Extremism, Free Speech and the Rule of Law70
evidences that legislation curtailing it has ‘no place’ in liberal democracy.62 Certainly, with each stage of
scrutiny yielding further questions and with litigation challenges to the Counter-Extremism Strategy now
also being mounted63 it seems less and less likely that the UK Counter-Extremism Bill will ever pass into law.
One scholar does stand out as having proffered a list of extremism traits that could potentially found
a rule-of-law compliant definition. Etymologically, to be ‘extreme’ is to be furthest from the centre.64 This
implies a normative assessment; a benchmark against which views, opinions and ideologies are judged.65
Extending his view of extremism as intrinsically violent, Schmid suggests that the key need in narrowing
extremism is to distinguish it from other political speech and behaviour that does not pose a fundamental
threat to liberal democracy. Thus he identifies twenty specific markers of ‘extremists’.66 Whilst caution must
be exercised in relying on these markers since context can shift the benchmark, Schmid’s list is very thor-
ough and, positively, hones in on extremist speech that betrays a violent mindset aligned with those who
commit terrorist acts. A definition of extremism adopting Schmid’s markers in their entirety arguably has
the potential to be very precise indeed, targeting a narrow range of harm.
Even use of Schmid’s list, though, does not address the matter of discrimination. The NGO joint sub-
mission to the UN referenced above additionally identified that extremism definitions frequently either
inadvertently encompass or are being deliberately used to suppress unwanted democratic debate, dissent
and minority opinions.67 This echoes Post’s contention that laws claiming to be objectively justified as
preventing ‘hate speech’ are in reality being deployed to enforce ‘norms of propriety’ in matters such
as race, nationality and ethnicity.68 Whilst targeted application is highly problematic it does not of itself
negate legality; however, laws containing inherent risks of discrimination are fatally undermined, and evi-
dence suggests that the risks of discrimination inherent in extremism definitions cannot be cured through
‘inclusivity’. The Global Counter-Terrorism Forum’s Ankara Memorandum 2014 recommends that to pre-
vent discrimination States should avoid identifying extremism with any particular religion, culture, ethnic
group, nationality or race.69 In line with this, and in a manner typical of the liberal agenda, the UK asserts
that it targets ‘the full spectrum of extremism: violent and non-violent, Islamist and neo-Nazi – hate and
fear in all their forms’.70 However, though prima facie non-discriminatory, this inclusionary statement is
equally disturbingly wide-ranging. Kundani expresses fear that, coupled with sweeping terms positively
defining extremism, it leaves troubling scope for manipulation of the term extremist and could well result
in the ‘demonisation’ of anyone holding radically fringe views, labelling them as having a ‘fanatical mind-
set’ rather than just a ‘possibly misguided opinion’.71 A further testament to the potential that ‘inclusive
approaches’ hold for widespread repression is the ‘unlikely coalition’ of individuals and groups in the UK
holding disparate and even opposing views that have joined forces to campaign implementation of the
planned extremism legislation.72
Therefore, and worryingly enough, given the extent of extremism policy and legislation existing and pend-
ing worldwide, this paper cannot conclude with any confidence that a definition of extremism compliant
with international law’s principles of legality can be constructed. In order to proceed, therefore, the remain-
der of this paper lightly and hesitantly assumes that with care and attention to detail it might theoretically
62 ARTICLE 19, ‘Joint Statement highlights serious concerns about proposed Counter-Extremism and Safeguarding Bill’ (23 May
2016) .article19.org/resources.php/resource/38384/en/uk:-joint-statement-highlights-serious-concerns-about-
proposed-counter-extremism-and-safeguarding-bill> accessed 9 June 2017.
63 E.g. “R (Butt) v SSHD [2017] EWHC 1930 (Admin)” without judgment pending as of 9 June 2017.
64 From the latin ‘extremus’ meaning ‘outermost’ (OED).
65 Posłuszna (n 54) 21–26.
66 Schmid (n 51) 21.
67 UN NGO Joint Submission (n 23).
68 Robert Post, ‘Hate Speech’ In: Hare, I and Weinstein, J, (eds.), Extreme Speech and Democracy (OUP 2009) 136. ‘The Guardian view
on the counter-extremism bill: think again about thought police’ The Guardian (30 May 2016) .theguardian.com/
commentisfree/2016/may/30/the-guardian-view-on-the-counter-extremism-bill-think-again-about-thought-police> accessed 9
June 2017.
69 Global Counterterrorism Forum (GCTF) Ankara Memorandum on Good Practices for a Multi-Sectoral Approach to Countering
Violent Extremism (CVE), designed to provide GCTF members and other interested stakeholders with a non-exhaustive list of good
CVE practices (February 2014) 3.
70 UK Counter-Extremism Strategy (n 5) 8.
71 Kundnani (n 37) 15, 28.
72 ‘An unlikely coalition warns of threats to free expression in Britain’ The Economist (24 October 2015)
com/blogs/erasmus/2015/10/faith-and-free-speech-britain> accessed 9 June 2017; UK ‘Defend Free Speech Campaign’
defendfreespeech.org.uk/> accessed 9 June 2017.
Shepherd 71
be possible for domestic legislation restricting free expression of extremist views to satisfy Article 19(3)
ICCPR’s criteria of legality.
Legitimate Reasons to Restrict Expressions of Extremism
Assuming extremism legislation to be legal, this section now considers whether extremism legislation does
or could serve any legitimate purpose. Article 19(3) ICCPR provides for two umbrella reasons to restrict free
expression: protecting national security, public order, public health or morals; and, respecting the rights or
reputations of others. As identified above, liberal States enacting extremism legislation claim that it links to
terrorism: the UK explicitly identifies extremism as posing an intense and palpable threat to life and limb,
democratic values and the fabric of society.73 Two parts of the umbrella are therefore potentially applicable:
protecting national security and respecting the rights of others. Taking each purpose in turn, this section
unpacks the relevant international law and evaluates whether extremism legislation does or could concep-
tually fit.
Protecting National Security
Determining whether extremism legislation protects national security comprises three stages: First, it must
be ascertained how ‘national security’ is defined within the ICCPR and what is required under the ICCPR
for national security to be legitimately invoked. Second, these identified legal standards must be applied to
delimit if and how expressions of extremism in fact threaten national security. Third, providing extremism
does in law and fact pose a national security threat, it must be established whether measures restricting it
are in practice genuinely directed at countering that threat.
‘National Security’ under the ICCPR
The first step towards evaluating whether the alleged threat posed by extremists’ exercise of their freedom
of expression is a matter of national security is to define a national security threat. There is, however, at
present no definitive international jurisprudence on what constitutes ‘national security’: respect for sover-
eignty grants States a wide discretion to self-define national security threats and pursue individually tailored
security policies.74 This lack of international definition is somewhat alarming: the UN Special Rapporteur
on the promotion and protection of the right to freedom of opinion and expression expressed severe con-
cerns in his 2013 report that an ‘amorphous’ concept of national security is ‘vulnerable to manipulation’ by
States wishing both to invade upon fundamental rights and cloak their actions in secrecy.75 Though written
in the context of surveillance, these concerns have equal relevance to extremism: problems of rule of law
compliance with vague notions of extremism are compounded when ‘national security’ is equally impossible
to pin down. Helpfully, however, the UN Human Rights Committee (‘the Committee’) has taken a critical
approach towards States invoking national security, robustly and repeatedly requiring States to identify
the precise nature of any asserted security threat and expressing its disapproval of un-evidenced claims in
striking tones.76 This positively indicates that though States may not be confined to any single conception
of ‘national security’ under the ICCPR they still need to produce strong evidence to back up any recourse to
this as a legitimate aim.77 For states to link extremism with national security, more is needed than assertions
that extremism-equals-terrorism.
Nonetheless, at present ‘national security’ tends towards a catch-all phrase, used to cover both internal
civil disturbances and external, global threats to sovereignty. Troublingly, such breadth facilitates deliberate
or inadvertent escalation of local threats to a higher plane, inherently justifying greater severity of measures
in response and directly impacting on the appropriate probative force of questions over necessity under
73 UK Counter-Extremism Strategy (n 5) 5–6.
74 E.g. Switzerland has a policy of neutrality whereas the USA seeks security through alliances: Amin Pashaye Amiri, Freedom of Infor-
mation and National Security: A Study of Judicial Review under US Law (Utz Verlag GmbH 2014) 20.
75 UNHRC, ‘Report of the Special Rapporteur on the promotion and protection of the right to freedom of opinion and expression’ (17
April 2013) UN Doc A/HRC/23/40, 58–60. See also Manfred Nowak, UN Covenant on Civil and Political Rights CCPR Commentary
(N.P. Engel 2005) 464.
76 See notably, Jong-Kyu Sohn v. Republic of Korea, Comm No 518/1992 (19 July 1995) UN Doc CCPR/C/54/D/518/1992; Tae Hoon
Park v. Republic of Korea, Comm No 628/1995 (3 November 1998) UN Doc CCPR/C/64/D/628/1995; Keun-Tae Kim v. Republic
of Korea Comm No 574/1994 (4 Januar y 1999) CCPR/C/64/D/574/1994; Mr. Jeong-Eun Lee v. Republic of Korea Comm No
1119/2002 (20 July 2005) UN Doc CCPR/C/84/D/1119/2002.
77 General Comment No 34 (n 15) 36 also affirms that the Human Rights Committee will not hesitate to take steps in any case
brought before it to determine for itself whether any particular threat warrants invoking national security to limit freedom of
expression.
Extremism, Free Speech and the Rule of Law72
Article 19(3)’s third limb. Soft law guidelines however offer precise and narrow definitions of ‘national secu-
rity’ and a strengthened application of these would be welcomed. The UN Siracusa Principles provide that
national security may only justify rights-restrictive measures where these are taken to protect ‘the existence
of the nation or its territorial integrity or political independence.’78 They also provide that national security
cannot be used as a pretext to impose vague or arbitrary limitations on fundamental rights.79 This means
that illegitimately expansive definitions of extremism cannot be remedied purely by oblique references
thereafter to national security. The Johannesburg Principles80 further specify that national security may only
be used to limit freedom of expression where there is a ‘direct and immediate connection’ between expres-
sions intending to incite violence and the likelihood of or occurrence of such violence.81 Nowak’s CCPR
Commentary also identifies ‘national security’ as a ‘political or military threat to the entire nation’, including
‘publication of a direct call to violent overthrow of the government in an atmosphere of political unrest’.82
Under these definitions, extremism only indirectly linked to violence could not be subsumed into the murky
waters of national security.
It is rational and coherent to limit ‘protecting national security’ to ‘preserving the safety of State territory
and protecting the integrity of its vital institutions from violent action’; adoption of a definition comprising
these criteria by both States and international bodies could vitally promote transparency and accountabil-
ity in State practice. Nonetheless, under the ICCPR as it stands States may apparently invoke this objective
against any perceived threat provided they can justify their reasoning. This being the case, the next question
to ask is; do extremists pose a national security threat?
Extremists as the Enemy Within
This paper accepts that extremism may be linked to terrorism. However, without more, this ultimately pos-
its terrorism as the threat to national security with extremism a mere warning signal. To ascertain whether
extremism could be identified as a discrete national security risk, this section reflects on an idea indepen-
dently but concurrently raised by three counter-terrorism scholars; namely, that society has in recent years
returned to a paradigm whereby States use their power to seek out and oust the ‘enemy within’.
Clavell, Lomell and Galli each powerfully argue that post-9/11 counter-terrorism approaches have revived
a dormant pattern of States perceiving the enemy to be not only abroad but also ever-present at home.83
Lomell and Clavell further suggest that this ‘enemy within’ model re-arose in society post-9/11 because that
event eroded the distinction between ‘national’ and ‘international’ security, triggering a global move towards
philosophical and operational security approaches that construct citizens as enemies.84 This notion has his-
torical credence: in ages past liberal States perceived and rejected, for example, communists as enemies
existing within society; ‘extremists’ are merely the contemporary iteration of this phenomenon. Further,
political positioning of extremism as a thread in the interlinked global threat of terrorism significantly
blurs security remits: domestic laws address matters within sovereign borders but local counter-extremism
measures are enacted in full awareness that internal expressions of extremism might causally result in harm
abroad, thus taking into account both domestic and international security considerations.
Clavell uniquely constructs a conceptual narrative of how ‘extremists’ became ‘enemies within’ liberal
States. She notes that in post-1980s Britain seemingly progressive and liberal models of crime prevention
provided the logic for more intrusive and less tolerant uses of State power. Pervasive ideas about ‘prevention’
led policing to negatively become about monitoring and extinguishing ‘deviant’ behaviour; marking out
‘others’ in society. Previously unwelcome fringe conduct was increasingly deemed completely intolerable.
Through this process, Clavell suggests, ‘extremists’ as ‘deviants’ were inexorably converted from holders of
odious viewpoints into downright dangerous beings. Clavell further contends that post-9/11 there has been
78 Siracusa Principles 1984 (n 25) Principle 29.
79 ibid Principle 31.
80 Johannesberg Principles on National Security, Freedom of Expression and Access to Information (1995). Adopted by experts in
international law, national security and human rights, endorsed by the then UN Special Rapporteur on Freedom of Opinion and
Expression and referred to by the UN Human Rights Council in their annual reports on freedom of expression.
81 ibid Principle 6.
82 Nowak (n 75) 464.
83 Gemma Galdon Clavell, ‘Urbanscapes of injustice and insecurity’ In: Hudson, B, and Ugelvik, S, Justice and Security in the 21st Cen-
tury: Risks, Rights and the Rule of Law (Routledge 2012); Heidi Mork Lomell, ‘Punishing the uncommitted crime’ In: Hudson, B, and
Ugelvik, S, Justice and Security in the 21st Century: Risks, Rights and the Rule of Law (Routledge 2012); Francesca Galli, The War on
Terror and Crusading Judges: Re-establishing the Primacy of the Criminal Justice System in Masferrer, A, (ed), Post 9/11 and the State
of Permanent Legal Emergency (Springer 2012) 153–175.
84 Lomell (n 83) 77; Clavell (n 83) 122, 126.
Shepherd 73
an amplified blurring of the line between local fears and foreign threats, leading to an obfuscation of the
remits of criminal law and defence policy in ‘the drive to fortify cities as well as borders against powerful,
unpredictable global actors bent on destruction’.85 She reasons that this domestic/international bound-
ary confusion redefined ‘deviants’ as posing not only a local but an international risk.86 Extrapolating from
this theory, extremists became enemies; no longer ‘mere’ domestic criminals but a more all-encompassing
national security problem.
Clavell’s assessment of State action as illiberal creep may be disputed: liberalism arguably contains a posi-
tive obligation to protect society from its destruction, which would under Clavell’s theory be the result were
‘enemies within’ not identified and dealt with. However, taken together with Lomell and Galli, Clavell’s
historical narrative does lucidly explain how extremism may legitimately be found to threaten national
security. Even referencing the narrow conception of national security set out within the Siracusa and
Johannesburg Principles there can be no dispute that enemies by their very nature target the institutions of
government and the existence of civil community. Consequently, once secured in position as ‘enemies’ the
security rationale underpinning any action taken against extremists would be firmly in place.
This is but one theory, though, and the potential practical ramifications of acting against extremists under
a conception of their being ‘enemies within’ are concerning. Enemies are by their very nature outside society,
not entitled to its protection and a risk to its existence. Regarding extremists as enemies therefore imme-
diately heightens the appropriate level of response to their presence, which has a significant impact on the
intensity of review conducted under Article 19(3)’s third criteria of necessity.
National vs Individual Security
‘Enemy’ or not, there still remains the question of counter-extremism’s intention: is it legitimately targeting
a defined national security threat or illegitimately aimed at assuaging a general ongoing sense of insecu-
rity? Domestic and international laws and policies appear increasingly focused on the goal of improving
‘individual security’ (subjectively defined feelings or perceptions of safety) rather than pursuing objectively
defined national security goals. Murphy, for example, described UK counter-terrorism policy as ‘exhibiting
characteristics of both risk-based government and moral panic’.87 Buhelt more broadly employed the beguil-
ing phrase ‘liquid fear’ to describe the imprecise and unclear dread with no clear address or cause that he
posits has become a decisive factor in national and international security policy-making since the singular
organisation identified in the initial aftermath of 9/11 has been revealed to be a more diffuse and scat-
tered network.88 Clavell further theorises that this ‘liquid fear’ coupled with enlarged definitions of security
which identify myriad risks and threats both locally and globally and have populaces demanding ever more
‘security’ to combat the ‘insecurity’ has distorted the meaning of national security, subsuming it within or
subverting it to individual security.89 The ‘enemy within’ construct could thus be both masking and fueling
State security aims that are not about securing the nation at all but rather merely tap into a general feeling
of peril that has been rising as a political power since September 2001. If this is so, even the broadest inter-
pretation of ‘national security’ under Article 19(3) ICCPR might not be satisfied.
The criminological concept of ‘moral panic’ particularly assists in explaining how legal distortion of
‘national’ into ‘individual’ security can occur. A term first developed and popularised by Cohen probing the
societal, political and legislative response to public disturbances by young people in a seaside town in 1960s
Britain, ‘moral panic’ describes a situation whereby public fear and State intervention grossly exceed an
objective threat posed to society.90 Cohen theorised that ‘moral panic’ does not happen spontaneously but is
the result of a complex interplay of actors exaggerating or distorting negative behaviours (real or perceived)
of certain individuals or groups. Media framing heightens the deviancy or criminality of identified ‘folk
devils’, presenting them as the embodiment of evil and making them the antagonists in the ensuing public
panic and State response. Political rhetoric positions the State as holding the moral high-ground against
this evil, fueling public agitation, and as rule of law enforcers are expected as part of their general remit to
detect, apprehend and punish evil, nebulous panic solidifies into disproportionately punitive legislation.
Cohen’s theory was originally limited to a relatively minor clash of a youth subculture with authority but was
85 Clavell (n 83) 126.
86 ibid 128.
87 Diego Acosta Arcarazo, Cian C Murphy, EU Security and Justice Law: After Lisbon and Stockholm (Hart Publishing 2014) 168.
88 Anders Folmer Buhelt, Policing the Law of Fear’ In: Hudson and Ugelvik (n 83) 188.
89 Clavell (n 83) 126.
90 Stanley Cohen, Folk Devils and Moral Panics: The Creation of the Mods and Rockers (Routledge 1972) 9, 28.
Extremism, Free Speech and the Rule of Law74
subsequently expanded and applied to other manifestations of ‘deviant’ behaviour,91 and, as with extremism,
his ideas had new life breathed into them post-9/11. Examining the USA response to that security breach
and tragedy, Rothe and Muzzatti described the US as a culture ‘embedded in fear’ and concluded that State
presentations of the threat of terrorism had generated a ‘moral panic’ according to Cohen’s precepts.92
It is arguable that contemporary presentations of ‘extremists’ equally subscribe to Cohen’s model. ‘Moral
panic’ is surely complemented and exacerbated by the paradigm of the ‘enemy within’ which transforms
deviancy into an active threat, increasing tension between individuals and groups. As the State wages war
on its own citizens it shifts from defending responses to concrete threats to protecting more diffuse matters
such as ‘social cohesiveness and identity’.93 This in turn fuels negative public perceptions of extremism, leads
to calls for ‘more security’ and results in legislation borne out of ‘liquid fear’. Cohen’s theory admittedly only
has partial applicability to extremism: a ‘moral panic’ in socio-criminal theory only exists to the extent that
the public press for State action against the ‘folk devils’ yet the extent of public backlash in Britain against
the impact of the Government’s extremism policies94 indicates that any panic about ‘extremists’ is mainly
pushed from a State level, not wholly against public sentiment but certainly without its complete blessing.
Still, when States invoke national security as the ‘legitimate’ aim in extremism legislation Cohen’s theory
does go some way towards supporting the possibility that this is a fallacy; States are in truth pursuing visions
of individual security.
Ultimately, given the legal scope to claim almost any end as national security, the link from extremism to
terrorism and the conceptual placing of extremists as ‘enemies within’, it may be concluded that extremism
legislation could potentially serve national security ends within the terms of Article 19(3) ICCPR. However,
the word ‘potentially’ is key. National security carries deeply embedded connotations of sovereign preroga-
tive. A certain level of transparency is vital in order to prevent the rule of law sliding into rule by executive
dictate. Accepting without further enquiry that legislation restricting free speech is enacted because extrem-
ism is a danger to national security may subconsciously negatively impact the intensity of review engaged
in when assessing the necessity of any such legislation. To guard against this, States must justify not just the
extent of their actions but also the underpinning rationale.
Respecting the Rights of Others
The second purpose that extremism legislation could potentially serve under Article 19(3) ICCPR is respect-
ing the rights of others. This is premised on extremists’ freedom of expression conflicting with rights held
by others in society. Balancing competing rights against one another is a core component of human rights
practice; a plethora of domestic and international jurisprudence exists giving preference to one individual
over another and identifying various factors given weight in the exercise. Despite its legal prevalence, how-
ever, the ‘balancing exercise’ is fraught with difficulty and controversy. Two central questions have relevance
for extremism legislation: which ‘rights’ are being respected and who are the ‘others’ concerned?
‘Rights’ under the ICCPR
The ICCPR contains no clear definition of a ‘right’.95 The UN Siracusa Principles specify that ‘when a conflict
exists between a right protected under the ICCPR and one which is not, recognition and consideration
should be given to the fact that the Covenant seeks to protect the most fundamental rights and freedoms’.96
This statement accepts that ‘rights’ may exist outside the bounds of those set down in international treaties.
UN General Comment No. 34 could possibly be read otherwise. It specifies that ‘rights’ ‘includes human
rights as recognized in the Covenant and more generally in international human rights law’.97 On one view,
this limits rights to those those explicitly delimited by existing legal documents. However, jurisprudence of
the European Court of Human Rights (‘ECtHR’) forms part of ‘international human rights law’ and compre-
hensively reviewing ECtHR case-law on balancing conflicting rights Bomhoff98 notes that the ECtHR takes
91 Erich Goode and Nachman Ben-Yehuda, Moral Panics: The Social Construction of Deviance (Wiley-Blackwell 1994) cited through
Rothe and Muzzatti (n 39) 330–331.
92 Rothe and Muzzatti (n 39) 332, 337.
93 Buhelt (n 89) 179.
94 Note the UK ‘Defend Free Speech Campaign’ (n 72).
95 Nowak (n 75) 463.
96 Siracusa Principles 1984 (n 25) Principle 36.
97 General Comment No. 34 (n 15) 28.
98 Jacco Bomhoff, ‘The Rights and Freedoms of Others: The ECHR and its peculiar category of conflicts between individual fundamen-
tal rights’ In: Brems (ed), Conicts Between Fundamental Rights (Intersentia 2008) 619–654.
Shepherd 75
a wide understanding of ‘rights’ extending far beyond those codified in the ECHR. Highlighting particularly
the decision in Otto-Preminger-Institut v. Austria,99 which protected a ‘right to religious feelings’, Bomhff con-
cludes there is currently next to nothing that would likely be excluded by the ECtHR as a legitimate ground
for the limitation of fundamental rights.100 In view of the lack of boundary on the category of ‘rights’ set by
the ECtHR and the close linguistic corollary between the ECHR and the ICCPR101 it may be concluded that
‘rights’ may be equally broadly defined under the ICCPR.
Such a sweeping approach has potentially devastating implications. Tsakyrakis102 forcefully argues that
international law’s ‘definitional generosity’103 risks losing sight of the moral message conveyed by demarcat-
ing only certain matters as ‘fundamental rights’.104 Tsakyrakis contends that human rights are not merely
‘quantities of freedom’ but protect people as ‘moral agents’.105 Consequently, he argues, jettisoning any
notion of quantifiable ‘rights’ and allowing any interest or consideration to compete as if a ‘right’ in a balanc-
ing process fatally compromises that which was originally denoted by lawmakers as being so important.106
Bomhoff too is concerned by this: though he fails to identify any limit to the term ‘rights’ he insists that one
must nonetheless implicitly exist as too broad an application of ‘rights’ risks undermining the integrity of
balancing as an enterprise.107 This is a reasonable anxiety. Definitional flexibility can be positive, enabling
courts to take account of evolving understandings of rights and provide better protection to vulnerable
individuals who don’t exactly fit within established categories. Flexibility of approach towards balancing is
also arguably useful in enabling economic, social and cultural rights to be openly and fairly weighed against
civil and political rights despite these being separated within the international legal order. But where ‘rights’
begin to be effectively created entirely outside established treaty frameworks the notion of a delimited set
of ‘rights’ guaranteed to all individuals because of our common humanity – upon which all of international
human rights law rests – worryingly begins to crumble.
Nonetheless, as the law stands, in the context of extremism it is possible that something as vague as a
‘right to feel secure’ could be used legitimately by States to restrict free speech. In fact, the marginally more
concrete ‘right to individual security’ parallels the emerging developmental idea of a right to ‘human secu-
rity’, which emphasises individual welfare in the right to security provision by States.108 These ‘rights’ in place
therefore, the next stage is to define the ‘others’ holding them who are in need of protection.
Identifying ‘Others’
Not only is there no limit to the ‘rights’ which may be at stake, no set criteria exists to identify the ‘others’
affected. Crucially, States must not through defining ‘others’ simply or inadvertently pit one extremist ideol-
ogy against another or illegitimately protect ‘moderate’ individuals from feeling threatened by those espous-
ing different, unwelcome ideologies. Certainly, it would seem illegitimate to regard ‘others’ as those liable to
have their voice ‘drowned out’ by ‘extremists’: part of the right to individual security is arguably cultivation of
and protection by the State of a strong political sphere, robustly able to entertain diverging perspectives and
counter-cultural viewpoints. In view of Schmid’s view above that the central marker of extremism should be
anti-liberal content, perhaps the ‘others’ could reasonably be simply all those who are members of a liberal
democracy. This fits particularly well for Article 19(3) in light of the fact that the ECHR exclusively deals
with rights as held by individuals but under the ICCPR the term ‘others’ may relate to persons individually
or as a group.109 Construing the issue as the harmful influence of extremism on society at large, the relevant
‘right’ becomes a community right to a secure civil society space. This being so, the ‘others’ could be regarded
broadly as all within the community seeking access to that space.
Thus it is straightforward, if instinctively troubling by its very simplicity, to find that extremism legisla-
tion serves the legitimate purpose of respecting the rights of others. However, if ‘rights’ and ‘others’ can be
anything it becomes exponentially more imperative for extremism to be tautly defined. Thankfully, the ease
99 Otto-Preminger-Institut v. Austria App No 13470/87 (ECtHR, 20 September 1994).
100 Bomhoff (n 98) 624.
101 See (n 20).
102 Stavros Tsakyrakis, ‘Proportionality: An assault on human rights?’ (2009) 7 Int J Const Law 468–493.
103 ibid 480.
104 ibid 479, 485, 488.
105 ibid 490.
106 ibid 482, 488, 492–493.
107 Bomhoff (n 98) 621.
108 See Roland Paris, ‘Human Security – Paradigm Shift or Hot Air?’ (2001) 26 International Security 88.
109 See General Comment No 34 (n 15) 28.
Extremism, Free Speech and the Rule of Law76
of passing this second hurdle within Article 19(3) is tempered by the limiting nature of Article 19(3)’s third
criteria of necessity, to which this paper now turns.
Need to Restrict Extremist Expressions
Having concluded that legislation restricting extremist speech could potentially be legitimately directed at
protecting national security or respecting the rights of others this section addresses the final criterion of
Article 19(3), questioning whether such legislation is needed to achieve either of these aims. To do so, it is
vital first to unpack how ‘necessity’ is defined and applied under the ICCPR to adjudicate the legitimacy of
restrictions on qualified fundamental rights: though it is a cornerstone of human rights law that interfer-
ences with qualified rights may extend only so far as is ‘necessary’ this phrase requires some clarification.
Necessity under the ICCPR
The established stricture of international human rights law dictating how far States may restrict non-abso-
lute fundamental rights is simply that measures imposed in pursuit of a legitimate purpose must not be
more restrictive than are ‘necessary’ to achieve that purpose. It is widely agreed that necessity is an adaptable
standard that takes account of both individual circumstances and the nature of the fundamental right at
stake; however, what precisely necessity entails and how it is or should be practically applied is not alto-
gether straightforward.
Necessity is firmly twinned within the ICCPR with the notion of proportionality. The UN has specifically
affirmed that Article 19(3) ICCPR deliberately intended the proportionality of rights-restrictive action110 to be
considered. It has further specified that to be necessary/proportionate, restrictions to the right to freedom
of expression must be ‘directly related’ to the need they claim to serve and the ‘least intrusive instrument’
for the purpose, taking into account the form of expression at issue as well as the means of its dissemina-
tion. There must be a ‘direct and immediate’ connection between the free expression at stake and the threat
its restriction is designed to counter.111 The UN Siracusa Principles also take a very narrow interpretation
of ‘necessity’, stipulating as general guidance that States must prove limitations to qualified rights do not
‘impair the democratic functioning of society’.112 In view of the central importance of freedom of expression
to democracy, this requirement places States under an onerous obligation with little scope for any restric-
tion to be justified. The UN Rabat Plan of Action further reiterates that free expression restrictions must be
targeted and recommends that they should respond to a ‘pressing social need’.113
Aimed at guiding States on how to balance Articles 19 and 20 ICCPR, the Rabat Plan’s principles and rec-
ommendations arguably apply irrespective of the provision under which the expression in question is in fact
categorised. Thus, two further points made therein are also relevant. First, given that the strength of harm
evaluation impacts on the extent to which interruption measures are warranted, the six factors identified
above for assessing whether a specific instance of speech ought to be prohibited or punished as incitement
logically have broader applicability to assessments of necessity. Second, it is noteworthy that a clear distinc-
tion is drawn between three types of expression: expression which constitutes a criminal offence; expression
below that threshold but justifying civil or administrative sanctions; and, expression lower again but that
raises a concern in terms of tolerance, civility and respect for the rights of others. This sliding scale gives
useful scope for nuanced approaches, especially as the Plan advocates viewing criminal sanctions as a ‘last
resort’.114
Interpretations of necessity under Article 19 ICCPR are further informed by the regional human rights
mechanisms’ robust attitude towards freedom of expression, particularly that of the ECtHR. The UN accords
entirely with the long-established ECtHR position that the right to freedom of expression must only be
restricted in very narrow circumstances, and the ECtHR has in recent years taken an increasingly protective
attitude towards free speech: analysing 35 years of case-law Voorhoof demonstrates how ECtHR judgments
now ever-more frequently uphold the right to freedom of expression and regularly emphasise the value for
democratic society in tolerance, broadmindedness, pluralism and participation in public debate.115 A limited
110 Faurisson v. France (n 30). Individual opinion by Elizabeth Evatt and David Kretzmer, co-signed by Eckart Klein (concurring) 8,
Individual opinion by Prafullachandra Bhagwati (concurring).
111 General Comment No 34 (n 15) 34–36.
112 Siracusa Principles 1984 (n 25) Principle 20.
113 Rabat Plan (n 32) 4. See also Siracusa Principles 1984 (n 25) Principle 10b; Sunday Times v. UK (n 22) 62.
114 Rabat Plan (n 32) 7.
115 Dirk Voorhoof, ‘The Right to Freedom of Expression and Information under the European Human Rights System: Towards a more
Transparent Democratic Society’ (2014) European University Institute Working Paper, RSCAS 2014/12, particularly 2, 6.
Shepherd 77
number of judgments handed down since Voorhoof’s paper do buck the trend he identifies; however, as the
majority of these cases concern statements made online there is rationality and strength in suggestions by
commentators that the shift in approach may be regarded as attributable and limited to teething discom-
fort in the ECtHR over the internet’s de facto provision of enhanced free speech opportunities.116 Overall,
the ECtHR’s approach indicates that there is very little scope for States to justify restrictions to free speech,
particularly to the level of criminal sanction, and suggestions of wider benefits to society flowing from
enhanced free expression protection117 adds to the reasons that Article 19(3) ICCPR should continue to be
interpreted narrowly.
Assessing Necessity
Concluding that a ‘strong’ standard of necessity is and should be applied where the right to freedom of expres-
sion is at stake, however, leaves untouched the question of how exactly how necessity/proportionality assess-
ments are or should be undertaken. Three central decisions of the UN Human Rights Committee concerning
freedom of expression and national security relevantly emphasise the impressionistic nature of ‘necessity’
assessments. In Tae Hoon Park the Committee was quite evidently unimpressed by South Korea invoking as
a security threat the ‘general situation’ in North Korea and the nature of North Korea’s communist ideolo-
gy.118 There, as again later in Keun-Tae Kim it stated disapprovingly that the ‘precise nature and extent’ of the
alleged threat posed by the applicants’ activities (respectively, membership of a student organisation discuss-
ing Korean unification and distribution of political material siding with North Korea) had not been adequately
identified, nor was there any evidence in either case of a need for criminal prosecution.119 Some years later, in
Jeong-Eun Lee (concerning conviction of a student for belonging to a political association regarded by South
Korea as ‘enemy-befitting’) the Committee rather tetchily stipulated that necessity required aversion of a ‘real
and not only hypothetical’ danger.120 What may be gleaned from these cases is that the Committee applies
a consistently exacting standard of necessity but shows no detailed assessment framework for its decision-
making process.
This is unhelpful when attempting to construct an overarching theory of necessity, and indeed generally
for transparency and accountability. The link between necessity and proportionality lends itself to a balanc-
ing test much as when individual rights are pitted against one another. Building on this, Gerards interest-
ingly has advocated for a novel two-fold test: first examine the suitability of particular means for the ends
pursued; then only if the chosen means appear to be both adequate and necessary does balancing come
into play.121 Such an approach could positively act to emphasise the need for measures to be underpinned
by objective justifications: as the ECtHR has recognised, especially where free expression abhorrent to liberal
democracy is concerned there is a vital need to prevent personal conviction from influencing judgments
about what is actually dangerous.122 The remainder of this section therefore relies on Gerard’s approach
when asking whether extremism legislation does or is ever likely to be able to meet the stringent standards
for necessity under Article 19(3), considering first the need to restrict extremist speech to protect national
security.
Necessity to Protect National Security
The international law framework established above effectively provides that to comply with Article 19(3)
ICCPR’s necessity requirement any restrictions to extremist speech premised on protecting national security
need to directly respond to the harm to the State likely to be otherwise inflicted and be at the minimal ade-
116 Oreste Pollicino, Fundamental Rights in the EU: A Matter for Two Courts (Hart Publishing 2015) 106; Neville Cox, ‘Delfi v. Estonia:
Privacy Protection and Chilling Effect’ (19 June 15) Verfassungsblog .verfassungsblog.de/en/delfi-v-estonia-privacy-
protection-and-chilling-effect/> accessed 25 July 2017; Lorna Woods, ‘Delfi v Estonia: Curtailing online freedom of expression?’
(18 June 15) EU Law Analysis Blog 5/06/delfi-v-estonia-curtailing-online.html> accessed
9 June 2017. Dissemination of extremist content via the internet is a major factual issue raising discrete questions of responsibility
and liability. These matters are beyond the scope of this paper, which does not concern itself with the method by which extremist
views are expressed, except insofar as to comment that availability of and access to extremist material online and measures which
can be realistically imposed to counteract content factors into any assessment of necessity.
117 Voorhoof (n 115) 1.
118 Tae Hoon Park (n 76) 7.2.
119 Keun-Tae Kim (n 76) 12.5.
120 Jeong-Eun Lee (n 76) 7.2.
121 Janneke Gerards, ‘How to improve the necessity test of the European Court of Human Rights’ (2013) 11 Int J Const Law 472.
122 Vejdeland v. Sweden App No 1813/07 (ECtHR, 9 May 2012), Concurring Opinion of Judge Spielmann, joined by Judge Nussberger,
citing Féret v. Belgium App No 15615/07 (ECtHR, 16 July 2009).
Extremism, Free Speech and the Rule of Law78
quate level of severity. Having examined how extremism links with violence in terrorism, identified national
security as being concerned with preventing violence and considered a theory of extremists as ‘enemies
within’ presenting a constant and insidious threat to national security, this section now asks to what extent
it is or might be necessary to restrict the freedom of expression enjoyed by extremists to serve the purpose
of national security.
Risks and Responses
The need to restrict expressions of extremism depends on the extent to which they pose a ‘direct and
immediate’ risk to national security. Assuming for present purposes that some need to restrict to protect
against extremism can be shown, determining the ‘precise nature and extent’ of any security risk posed by
extremist speech, and thus the level of restriction on free expression justified, requires examination of the
speech’s content and context. Though each individual situation will be unique, the particularly vocal nature
of ‘extremists’ could be a relevant consideration: Schmid notes that ‘extremists’ often actively recruit to their
cause; intensity and fervour heightening their agitation and leading them to gain disproportionate promi-
nence.123 When coupled with Buyse’s finding that when one interpretation or discourse gains the ‘upper
hand’ and stifles alternative voices the danger of violent escalation is larger,124 this circumstance could be
used to justify greater intrusion into extremist speech.
States, however, must be careful that in the vigor of their counter-extremism approaches they do not ille-
gitimately focus on eradicating extremist speech from public dialogue to the exclusion of advancing other
equally or more needed security measures. The UN Terrorism Rapporteur’s 2016 Report criticised States
for paying attention to only those issues ‘most appealing’ to them and ‘shying away’ from more complex
matters.125 States must also not exaggerate risks: arguably, extremism measures should always be wholly
exceptional as the small numbers of people that eventually get radicalised and take terrorist action make
intrusion into this core democratic right generally disproportionate. Indeed, extending this line of reason-
ing and echoing the point above that indirect and stretched connections between speech and violent action
may mean that only Article 20(2) impositions on extremist speech are justified, domestic legislation directly
outlawing and penalising incitement to terrorist acts – a product of States’ obligations under international
law to combat terrorism – arguably suffices without extremism legislation at all to cover any risks to security
posed by extremists in society.126
Cram and Malik further argue that it is fallacious to assume that curtailing extremist speech negates exist-
ence of its underlying ideology and goals. They comment that extremists may be willing to make superficial
concessions in service of their aims but ‘moderate’ speech may mask an uncompromising worldview that
is shared only with select audiences. Restrictions on extremist speech have no impact on these private
extremists, dimming the urgency of restricting fundamental rights to protect.127 Civil sanctions might also
be regarded as less severe than criminal penalties but they have the insidious potential to impact on indi-
viduals and groups otherwise untainted by the label of extremism: for example, closing a community centre
to prevent gatherings of certain extremists will have a knock-on suppressive effect on non-related, entirely
innocuous activities. Ultimately, therefore, whilst it might be possible to make a case for some need to
restrict extremist speech, the need ever for severe sanctions, particularly to the level of criminal punishment,
is highly suspect.
More Speech, not Less
Adding to this, there are strong empirical indications that limiting the range of expression in society might
not effectively counter the threats posed by extremism: on the contrary, banning or criminalising public
expressions of extremist views might actually heighten the risk of violence ultimately occurring. As a matter
of law, if interfering with freedom of expression proves to be unsuitable to achieve the aim of protecting
national security even legislation imposing only low-level restrictions on extremist expression might be
disproportionate: Gerards argues that in necessity assessments any negative consequences of action for
123 Schmid (n 51) 5.
124 Buyse (n 52) 786, 795.
125 UN Terrorism Rapporteur 2016 Report (n 1) 15.
126 See e.g. UNSC Res 1456 (20 January 2003) UN Doc S/RES/1456/2003; UNSC Res 1624/2005 (n 43). Note comments of the UK
Joint Human Rights Committee to this end (n34), though, of course, domestic counter-terrorism law must itself comply with inter-
national law. See particularly General Comment No. 34 (n 15) 46.
127 Ian Cram, Terror and the War on Dissent (Springer 2009) 17; Maleiha Malik, ‘Extreme Speech and Liberalism’ In: Hare, I and Wein-
stein, J, (eds.), Extreme Speech and Democracy (OUP 2009) 115.
Shepherd 79
fundamental rights are of vital relevance and measures harming fundamental rights but failing to benefit
anyone or to achieve the desired results will not be reasonable, effective or necessary.128
There are four reasons that, at least for some individuals, silencing extremist messages exacerbates rather
than alleviates potential damage. First, suppression of extremist views can cause alienation and disaffec-
tion: identified factors in the road to radicalisation and terrorist violence.129 Second, a focus on eliminating
extremist speech can prevent meaningful engagement with those most at risk of radicalisation130 and take
extremist conversations underground, preventing vulnerable individuals from being exposed to contrary
views.131 Third, censorship gives credence to claims by certain extremists that one of the most core freedoms
of democracy is denied to those who argue against it, increasing the ‘level’ of extremism some individuals
will be willing to subscribe to132 - notably, the UN’s ‘Plan of Action’ suggests that extremists ‘provoke States
into overreacting then exploit ill-conceived government action for their own propaganda ends’.133 Fourth,
repressive action taken by the State against extremist speech feeds two dangerous illusions: that clashing
with authority is a ‘testament to truth’, and ‘sinister attribution error’ whereby ever ything negative is con-
strued as a plot.134
The negative effect of State narratives of extremism leading inescapably to violence which attach to
restrictive measures also has a potentially exacerbating effect on the risk of extremist speech escalating to
violence. With regard to the UK, Kundnani contends that the official narrative of extremism as an ‘embedded
problem’ unhelpfully ‘promotes and reinforces false stereotypes, distorts public discourse and fosters social
divisions’, all of which increases the likelihood of violence ultimately occurring.135 Referencing Buyse’s con-
clusion, actively marginalising people by labelling their voice extremist and banning or criminalising expres-
sion of their views in public democratic dialogue is likely only to ‘harden boundaries between groups, instil
fear and push individuals towards embracing violent action as a vehicle to advance their access to equality,
development and freedom of [ideology]’.136
Cumulatively, therefore, the need to and wisdom of silencing the voices of extremists to secure the nation
appears seriously contraindicated. There is strength in the argument that any threat to national security
posed by extremism should be fought with human rights, not by compromising them.137 NGOs notably con-
sistently advocate for more rather than less speech; a joint statement criticising the UK’s Counter-Extremism
Bill, for example, called for ‘soaring confidence in our values and the society we seek to build together’ and
the defeat of terrorism through freedom not fear.138 The UN, OSCE, OAS and ACHPR freedom of expression
representatives additionally chose to emphasise in a 2015 joint statement that ‘censorship is not an effec-
tive response to extremism’.139 States have positive obligations under international law to ‘ensure that all
groups in society have access to opportunities to make their voices heard’140 and to obstruct free speech
where it poses a direct threat of terrorism:141 these imperatives could arguably be interpreted broadly and
deployed (if individual circumstances warranted) to cover more indirect risk-filled expressions of extremism
128 Gerards (n 123) 469–470.
129 RUSI, ‘Drivers of Violent Extremism’ (n 44) 14–16.
130 ibid 19.
131 ibid 21.
132 Cram (n 127) 20.
133 UN Plan of Action to Prevent Violent Extremism (n 6) 15.
134 Bartlett and Birdwell, ‘From Suspects to Citizens: Preventing Violent Extremism in a Big Society’ (2010) Demos Think-Tank Report
18.
135 Kundnani (n 37) 30, 32, 37.
136 Buyse (n 52) 782, 789–790; RUSI, ‘Drivers of Violent Extremism’ (n 44) 31–33.
137 Demos Think Tank Editorial, ‘Even with the face-lift of the Queen’s speech, the Extremism Bill is misguided and counter-productive’
(20 May 2016) .demos.co.uk/even-with-this-weeks-face-lift-the-extremism-bill-is-misguided-and-counter-produc-
tive/> accessed 25 July 2015. ‘The future of safeguarding against extremism lies in. . . teaching young people how to recognise
extremist propaganda, understand whenthey are being manipulated, and identify poor arguments inorder to build their resilience
to the material they will inevitably be exposed to’.
138 Joint Statement (n 62). See also Expert Workshop on the Prohibition of National, Racial or Religious Hatred ‘Joint submission by
the Special Rapporteurs on freedom of opinion and expression, freedom of religion or belief, and racism, racial discrimination,
xenophobia and related intolerance’ (2011): ‘The strategic response to hate speech is more speech: more speech that educates
about cultural differences; more speech that promotes diversity; more speech to empower and give voice to minorities . . . ’.
139 UN, OAS, OSCE, ACHPR Freedom of Expression Representatives, ‘Joint Declaration on Freedom of Expression and responses to
conflict situations’ (2015). .ohchr.org/EN/NewsEvents/Pages/DisplayNews.aspx?NewsID=15921&LangID=E#sthash.
JwvqENaK.dpuf> accessed 9 June 2017.
140 ibid.
141 See (n 127).
Extremism, Free Speech and the Rule of Law80
and prevent harm. In view of this, this paper tentatively suggests that Article 19(3)’s test of necessity is not
or is unlikely to be met by extremism legislation premised on protecting national security.
Necessity to Respect the Rights of Others
In light of the above conclusion, this paper finally asks whether the test of necessity under Article 19(3)
alternatively is or can be met by conceiving extremism legislation as aiming to respect the rights of others.
‘Respecting’ rather than ‘protecting’ suggests prima facie that there is an even lesser need for stringent cur-
tailment and criminalisation; however, recalling the operative paradigm of extremism begetting terrorism it
may still be viable under this heading to justify some restriction on extremist speech.
Restricting Intolerance
Different conceptual understandings of liberalism alter the point at which it is deemed necessary to exclude
a portion of free speech from civil society space in order to respect the rights of others. This paper ear-
lier supported Schmid’s notion that the version of legality in respect of extremism may be allowed to be
restricted, if at its core, it is anti-liberal, and this conclusion returns in relevance here. When assessing neces-
sity, the liberal State usually neutrally weighs rights against each other, making a content-empty assess-
ment of whether a particular contested expression should prevail. Nehustan, however, forcefully rejects this
approach. He contends that such neutrality undercuts the liberal State’s positive duty to promote human
flourishing by protecting certain values and ways of life. Backing the ECtHR tradition of taking a more
content-based approach to regulating speech, Nehustan encourages all liberal States to be actively biased;
to take the content of expression into account when balancing it against competing rights and provide less
protection to anti-liberal expressions.142 Under Nehustan’s conception of liberalism it arguably becomes
necessary to take active steps to restrict those espousing extremist ideologies in order to prevent them poi-
soning civil society space.
Nehustan’s vision of ‘perfectionist liberalism’ perceives the State not as a neutral spectator in rival notions
of ‘the good life’ but as an active participant responsible for creating the environment in which a particular
conception of ‘the common good’ may be achieved.143 ‘Perfectionist liberalism’ as promoted by Nehustan
tolerates only a certain level of illiberal behaviours and opinions running counter to the liberal ‘goods’ of
autonomy, freedom and equality.144 Nehustan does not contend that the content of expression alone is suf-
ficient to justify its curtailment and he asserts that complete prohibition of offensive expressions should
be ‘extremely rare’, but he does perceive content as relevant and proclaims that intolerance should not be
tolerated: that which is offensive to the liberal ear should be curtailed by the State in order to protect ‘worth-
while’ freedom.145 For Nehustan the ear offended is also relevant: he contends that liberal States should be
more willing to restrict expressions when defending liberal offended persons than when defending illiberal
offended persons.146
Applying the UN Rabat Plan terminology to Nehustan’s philosophy, it arguably serves a ‘pressing social
need’ to restrict extremist speech since protecting the middle-ground in society respects the rights of all to
have access to a free and open democratic discourse. In an earlier echo of this, Post asserts that censoring
expression could be justified when allowing it would alienate all other citizens from participating in public
discourse: silencing a minority serves to protect the very existence of public discourse.147 When taking into
consideration again the volume of extremist voices, the need to ensure a full range of views can be expressed
could make it acceptable for concerns over extremists occupying a disproportionate part of the public
sphere to inform States’ pursuit of extremism legislation.148 Running counter to liberal values, extremist
expressions warrant little protection.
Nehustan’s construction of liberalism, however, arguably goes too far in countenancing liberal State inter-
ference with individual freedom. The UN-identified role for States is to provide an adequate framework for
persons to achieve their full potential. It places a ‘special emphasis’ on strengthening pluralistic societies
142 Jossi Nehustan, ‘Offensive Expression: The Limits of Neutral Balancing Tests and the Need to Take Sides’ (2016) 16 Human Rights
Law Review 1–28.
143 ibid 5, 16.
144 ibid 6–7.
145 ibid 7–8, 17.
146 ibid 13.
147 Post (n 68).
148 UK Counter-Extremism Strategy (n 5) 32: ‘We must be careful to only give a platform to the right people’.
Shepherd 81
including fully protecting the right to espouse minority or dissenting views.149 Established international
law protects with particular fervor speech at the fringes of democracy: it is quite clear from Handyside and
Voorhoof’s extensive analysis of more recent ECtHR judgments that even under a content-based approach to
expression distasteful and bigoted views are strongly protected. Extremists are precisely the type of minority
whose free expression is in need of protection and a secure democracy has no need to fear any disagree-
ment with its precepts, nor even challenges to its very foundation. Permitting extremist views to form part
of civil society dialogue arguably strengthens rather than undermines the democratic sphere. The potential
negative impact on commitments to extremism caused by restriction is again relevant, as is the argument
that rights are respected through an increase in, as opposed to a reduction of, free speech. Thus, this paper
argues that it is likely unsustainable to claim any need within the terms of Article 19(3) ICCPR to restrict
expressions of extremism to respect the rights of others.
Respecting Rights through Security
In concluding this section, this paper contends that whether liberalism can justify restrictions on expres-
sions of extremism or not, the idea of ‘respecting rights through increasing security’ is in any event a
fundamentally flawed concept. The UN posits security as needed instrumentally to enable individuals to
pursue autonomous life plans or safeguard natural rights150 but invoking a ‘right to security’ to justify
rights-restrictive counter-extremism measures is highly problematic. Examining the philosophical basis for
a ‘right to security’, Lazarus argues that the tendency to ‘securitize’ rights must be resisted: where security
is used as the prism to view other rights, she submits, the liberty it is invoked to promote is in fact subtly
downgraded, stripped of richness and nuance.151 Similarly, Gearty contends that increasing security so that
rights may be freely exercised fatally undermines the integrity of the human rights enterprise. He states
that the easiest security response to an invisible threat (note again here the extremist as an ‘enemy within’)
is to suspect entire communities of being evil. Placing whole populations under suspicion, however, he
notes, transforms even ‘moderate’ individuals from human rights subjects into objects of control. A focus
on ‘security’ thus insidiously ‘redefines’ rights such that their repression is deemed necessary to ensure
their overall survival.152
Ironically, therefore, in the process of promoting security anti-liberal objectives of extremists are facili-
tated rather than frustrated. Pap further argues that as society perceives ‘security’ not as an objectively
determined social condition but a socio-psychological construction, desire for ‘more security’ incrementally
creates a tyrannical state. In consequence, ‘prevention’ becomes a ‘blank cheque’: if no violent terrorist
attack occurs, governments can credit their counter-extremism security measures; any attack that does occur
substantiates political will to further increase rights-restrictive regulations.153 Taken together, these views
support the conclusion that a politically-asserted ‘need’ for security does not equate to Article 19(3) neces-
sity. It does not lawfully follow that because a minority holding extreme views is suspected of connection
with terrorist activity that their entitlements to core rights and freedoms can be swept away for the sake of
a putative gain to the security of the majority.
Conclusion
Internationally, security discourse has since September 2001 pushed extremism to the forefront of global
and domestic political agendas, establishing this as the ‘threat’ which needs to be confronted to prevent
future violent terrorist action. But liberal States enacting increasing numbers of domestic laws impacting
on fundamental rights has concerning implications for the rule of law. It insidiously empowers authoritar-
ian States to justify repressive laws, which may then be nefariously applied outside the protection provided
by strong due process rules and procedures, and questions hover over whether laws that curtail expressions
of extremism comply with the established precepts of international human rights law. Restricting public
declarations of extremist ideology (whether spoken, written or symbolic) clashes with the core democratic
149 UNHRC Res 27/31 (23 September 2014) UN Doc A/HRC/27/L.24.
150 id.
151 Liora Lazarus, ‘The Right to Security’, In: Cruft, R, Liao, S, M, and Renzo, M, Philosophical Foundations of Human Rights (OUP 2015)
423.
152 Gearty (n 4) 107–108.
153 András László Pap, ‘Constitutional Exceptionalism’, In: Hudson and Ugelvik (n 83). The outworking of this may be seen in the UK’s
increasingly restrictive approach towards internet freedoms; consider the Queen’s Speech 2017 (n 10): ‘In the light of the terrorist
attacks in Manchester and London, my government’s counter-terrorism strategy will be reviewed to ensure that the police and
security services have all the powers they need. . . .’.
Extremism, Free Speech and the Rule of Law82
right to freedom of expression as enshrined in Article 19 ICCPR, and political claims of ‘necessity’ do not
equate to legal justification. This paper has thus asked from a theoretical standpoint if and how domestic
laws banning or criminalising extremist speech could comply with Article 19(3)’s tripartite test for the
legitimacy of rights-restrictive measures. Article 19(3)’s criteria are cumulative: all must be met for rights-
restrictive measures to be lawful; however, interrogating each in turn this paper has uncovered difficulties
at every stage.
Satisfying the first criteria of legality appears an almost insurmountable obstacle. UN documents and
State practice evidence that suppressing extremist speech is premised on preventing terrorism, with which
promulgation of anti-liberal hate-filled extremist ideologies has been empirically linked. Given that the
underlying and overriding motivation for extremism legislation infringing on the right to freedom of expres-
sion is a matter politically affecting the international community it would be highly beneficial to adopt
an international law definition of extremism. Codifying extremism internationally could lessen the risk of
problematic or illegitimate domestic definitions and frustrate both authoritarian and liberal State attempts
to subvert approved political rationale into illegitimately repressive laws and activities. Whether codifying
domestically or internationally, however, legally defining extremism is something of a labyrinthine endeav-
our: States and academics alike have struggled to articulate a sufficiently narrow and precise version of this
concept. Legitimate restrictions to the right to free speech can be carved out only by carefully crafted terms;
problematically, however, exactly identifying the markers of extremism that connect with the threat of ter-
rorism without including purely fringe or offensive but non-violent views appears a near-impossible feat
when taking into account the need also to avoid discrimination. This being so, there are strong grounds to
suggest that only expressions of extremism that amount to incitement to hate, violence or discrimination
and thus fall within the significantly narrower spectrum of expressions that must be expunged from society
according to Article 20(2) can be legitimately curtailed. However, though this paper is very hesitant to sug-
gest that any sufficiently narrow and precise definition of extremism could be formulated to be legal under
Article 19(3), it does tentatively suggest that Schmid’s detailed list of extremism features could be a valuable
resource.
Assuming that extremism can be legally defined under the terms of Article 19(3) and focusing on extrem-
ism as a root of terrorism, this paper has found it relatively simple to prove that restricting extremist speech
is genuinely aimed at serving a legitimate purpose; either protecting national security or respecting the
rights of others. Concerns for the rule of law under this second criterion of Article 19(3) in fact mostly arise
precisely due to the relative ease of justification; there being few legal constraints on the definitions of
‘national security’, ‘rights’ or ‘others’.
Nonetheless, complexities with meeting the threshold for necessity under Article 19(3) stall any cavalier
conclusions of lawfulness. The vital importance of the right to freedom of expression for democracy runs
as a golden thread throughout approaches to its restriction and particularly where necessity is reviewed
the high value placed upon free speech imbues assessments of the need to limit it with an unspoken bias
against curtailment. This hesitancy is only heightened by the multiplicity of issues surrounding the defini-
tion of extremism and the breadth of scope available to claim legitimate purposes are served. Questions of
necessity are always highly context-specific and in determining whether any restriction to extremist free
speech is needed the actual expression in issue will be relevant as will the sanction applied. As a matter
of theory, however, it is highly dubious whether extremist speech can ever justifiably be limited to pro-
tect national security or respect the rights of others. As far as national security is concerned, the line from
extremist speech to terrorist action is filled with other factors and branches and empirical evidence strongly
counter-indicates the need to restrict extremist speech to prevent terrorist violence, suggesting that in fact
the very restrictions intended to prevent may have an opposing emboldening effect. The need to restrict
freedom of expression to respect the rights of others is also suspect. Though some forms of liberalism
would support suppressing the rights of those at the edge to ensure the voices of those in the middle are
not ‘drowned out’ it is precisely those whose speech is counter-cultural or even odious that urgently need
the protection of human rights law: the minority needs to be protected against the majority, not the other
way around. Tolerating the presence of extremist speech does not mean agreement with its content and
robust disagreement with extremism increases the opportunity for those who do disagree to participate in
dialogue, strengthening freedom of expression for all in society.
Ultimately, having highlighted and explored the nuances involved in enacting extremism legislation this
paper takes a cautious approach to making definitive findings. It does not argue that extremism legislation
can never satisfy the high standards of international human rights law but it does conclude that to be lawful
Shepherd 83
domestic extremism legislation needs exceedingly tight definitional terms and in view of the fundamental
importance of free speech for democracy very careful consideration must be given to the nature, reason for
and extent of any restrictive measures and sanctions. Extremist ideologies may be abhorrent to liberal soci-
ety but this does not mean that those professing such views have no legal right to say their piece.
Competing Interests
The author has no competing interests to declare.
How to cite this article: Amy Shepherd, ‘Extremism, Fre e Speech and the Rule of Law: Evaluating the Compliance
of Legislation Restricting Extremist Expressions with Article 19 ICCPR’ (2017) 33(85) Utrecht Journal of
International and European Law pp. 62–83, DOI: https://doi.org/10.5334/ujiel.405
Submitted: 07 April 2017 Accepted: 24 July 2017 Published: 31 August 2017
Copyright: © 2017 The Author(s). This is an open-access article distributed under the terms of the Creative
Commons Attribution 4.0 International License (CC-BY 4.0), which permits unrestricted use, distribution, and
reproduction in any medium, provided the original author and source are credited. See http://creativecommons.org/
licenses/by/4.0/.
OPEN ACCESS
Utrecht Journal of International and European Law
is a peer-reviewed open access
journal published by Ubiquity Press.

To continue reading

Request your trial

VLEX uses login cookies to provide you with a better browsing experience. If you click on 'Accept' or continue browsing this site we consider that you accept our cookie policy. ACCEPT